| Wis. | Jan 15, 1866

Dixon, C. J.

The court below, both as to the instructions given and those refused, seems to have totally misconceived or misapplied the maxim, Qui facitper alium facitper se; or, what is the same in principle and more usually and appropriately applied with reference to actions ex delicto, the maxim, Respondeat superior. The master is always liable to third persons for the negligence or omission of duty of his servant while acting within the scope of his employment. If a servant drive his master’s carriage or cart so negligently as to overturn another carriage, or to run over an individual and do him an injury, the master is liable for the damages. The maxim, Respondeat superior, is applied in such a case, upon grounds of policy and security. It is founded upon the principle that it is the duty of every man, in the management of his own affairs, whether by himself or by his agents or servants, so to conduct them as not to injure another ; and if he does not do so, and another is thereby injured, he shall answer for the damage. If the injury be done by a servant in the course of his employment, it is, in contemplation of law, so far the act of the master, that the latter is civilly responsible therefor. Qui faeit per alium facit per se. But this maxim is applicable only as between the master or principal and third persons. It presupposes that the parties stand to each other in the relation of strangers, between whom there is no privity ; and has no application as between *410tbe master and Ms negligent servant, or tbe principal and bis agent, wbo bas so unskillfully or carelessly conducted bis business as to cause bim damage. As between tbe master and a stranger, tbe servant represents tbe master, and tbe master is responsible; but as between tbe master and tbe servant wbo bas committed tbe wrong or violated bis duty no less to tbe master than to tbe stranger, no sucb rule prevails. A servant is directly liable to bis master for any damage occasioned by bis negligence or misconduct, whether sucb damage be direct to tbe property of tbe master, or arise from tbe compensation wbicb tbe master bas been obliged to make to third persons for injuries sustained by them. To apply the maxim in sucb a case would be an utter perversion of it, and destructive of all liability on tbe part of servants. Tbe servant in sucb case represents, not tbe master, but himself. It is bis own negligence and misconduct for wbicb be is required to answer; and, in this respect, be stands upon tbe same footing as any other wrong-doer. In tbe case above supposed, tbe master, having paid tbe damage caused by tbe negligence of bis servant in running over a stranger, may sue tbe servant for tbe same act of negligence, to recover back tbe money paid. It would be strange if tbe servant, in answer to sucb an action, could say: “Be-spondeat superior. I was your servant at tbe time of tbe injury ; my act was your act, my negligence your negligence; and therefore you cannot recover.” Sucb an answer would be absurd enough; and yet tbe objection of the plaintiff to tbe claim of tbe defendants seems scarcely less so. It is insisted, and tbe jury were instructed, that tbe defendants are responsible for their servant Nathaniel Harmon’s negligence, if any, in this case, to tbe same extent as they, tbe defendants, would have been if they bad been in tbe place of Harmon, and done tbe same acts.” It is clear that under this instruction there could be no recovery against Harmon under any circumstances, whether suit were brought against bim alone or jointly with tbe present plaintiff. But why, if correct, ought not tbe doc-*411line to have been, carried one step further* and thus have saved any instruction as to the negligence of Harmon ? If the defendants in this action are responsible for the negligence of Harmon, “ to the same extent as they would have been if they had been in the place of Harmon and done the same acts,” why are they not responsible for the negligence of his fellow servant, the plaintiff? And why were the jury not instructed, as to the plaintiff, that it was the same as if the defendants had been in his place and had done the same acts ? This would have ended the controversy at once, since it is clear that if the defendants themselves killed the horses, they have no cause of complaint against either of their servants. The answer to these and similar propositions has already been given. Between the master and his servant, as to the wrongs committed by the servant without the assent or direction of the master, the servant does not stand in the place of his master, and if two or more servants, though acting independently of each other, are each at the same time guilty of a wrong which contributes to the injury of the master, all or either of them are liable to the master to the full extent of the injury, the same as other wrong-doers. The doctrine in such a case is correctly stated by Tendal, C. J., in Davis v. Garrett, 6 Bing., 716 [19 E. C. L., 215], that no wrong-doer can be allowed to apportion or qualify his own wrong; and that, as a loss has actually happened, whilst his wrongful act was in operation and force, which is fairly attributable to his wrongful act, he cannot set up as a defense that there was another or more immediate cause of the loss, acting upon the subject matter at the same time, or the bare possibility of a loss if his wrongful act had never been done.

By the Court. — The judgment is reversed, and a new trial awarded.

© 2024 Midpage AI does not provide legal advice. By using midpage, you consent to our Terms and Conditions.