28 F. Cas. 686 | E.D. Pa. | 1855
Before entering upon the question immediately before me at this time, it is proper that I should advert to the past action of this court in the case of Passmore Williamson, and to the considerations that led to it. I do this the rather, because in some of the judicial reviews to which it has been submitted collaterally, after an ex parte argument it does not seem to me to have been fully apprehended. I begin with the writ which originated the proceeding.
The writ of habeas corpus is of immemorial antiquity. If is deduced by the standard writers on the English law from the great charter of King John. It is unquestionable, however, that it is substantially of much earlier date; and it may be referred without improbability, to the period of the Roman invasion. Like the trial by jury, it entered into the institutions of Rome before the Christian era, if not as early as the times of the republic. Through the long series of political struggles which gave form to the British constitution, it was claimed as the birthright of every Englishman, and our ancestors brought it with them as such to this country; At the common law, it issued whenever a citizen was denied the exercise of his personal liberty, or was deprived of his rightful control over any member of his household, his wife, his child, his ward, or his servant It issued from the courts of the sovereign, and in his name, at the instance of any one who invoked it, either for himself or another. It commanded, almost in the words of the Roman edict—“De libero homine exhibendo” (D. 43, T. 29),—that the party under detention should be produced before the court, there to await its decree. It left no discretion with the party to whom it was addressed. He was not to constitute himself the judge of his own rights or of his own conduct; but to bring in the body, and to declare the cause wherefore he had detained it; and the judge was then to determine whether that cause was sufficient in law or not Such in America, as well as England, was the well known, universally recognized writ of habeas corpus.
When the federal convention was engaged in framing a constitution for the United States, a proposition, was submitted to it by one of the members, that “the privileges and benefits of the writ of habeas corpus shall be enjoyed in this government in the most expeditious and ample manner; and shall not be suspended by the legislature except upon the most urgent and pressing occasions.” See the Msdison Papers (vol. 3, p. 1365). The committei to whom this was referred for consideration, would seem to have regarded the privilege in question as too definitely implied in the idea of free government to need formal assertion or confirmation; for they struck out' that part of the proposed article in which it was affirmed, and retained only so much as excluded the question of its suspension from the ordinary range of congressional legislation. The convention itself must have concurred in their views; for in the constitution, as digested, and finally ratified, and as it stands now, there is neither enactment nor recognition of the privilege of this writ, except as it is implied in the provision that it shall not be suspended. It stands then under the constitution of the United States, as it was under the common law of English America, an indefeasible privilege, above the sphere of ordinary legislation.1 I do not think it necessary to argue from the words of this article, that the congress was denied the power of limiting or restricting or qualifying the right, which it was thus forbidden to suspend. I do not, indeed, see that there can be a restriction or limitation of a privilege which may not be essentially a suspension of it, to some extent at least, or under some circumstances, or in reference to some of the parties who might otherwise have enjoyed it. And it has appeared to me. that if congress had undertaken to deny altogether the exercise of this writ by the federal courts, or to limit its exercise to the few and rare cases that might peradventure find their way to some one particular court, or to declare that the writ should only issue in this or that class of cases, to the exclusion of others in which it might have issued at the common law, it would be difficult to escape the conclusion, that the ancient and venerated privilege of the writ of habeas corpus had not been in some degree suspended, if not annulled. But there has been no legislation or attempted legislation by congress, that could call for an expansion of this train of reasoning. There was one other writ, which, in the more recent contests between the people and the king, had contributed signally to the maintenance of popular right. It was the writ of scire facias, which had been employed to vindicate the rights of property, by "vacating the monopolies of the crown. Like the writ of habeas corpus, it founded itself on the concessions of Magna Charta; and the two were the proper and natural complements of each other. The First congress so regarded them. The protection of the citizen against arbitrary exaction and -unlawful restraint, as it is the essential object of all rightful government, would present itself as the first great duty of the courts of justice that were about to be constituted. And if, in defining their ju-
The language of the act of congress re-fleets the history of the constitutional provision. It enacts [1 Stat. 81] “that all the before mentioned courts . of the United States” (the supreme, circuit and district) "shall have power to issue writs of scire fa-cias, habeas corpus and all other writs not specially provided for by statute which may be necessary for the exercise of their respective jurisdictions and agreeable to the principles and usages of law.” I am aware that it has sometimes been contended or assumed, without, as it seems to me, a just regard to the grammatical construction of these words, that the concluding limitation applies to all the process of the courts, the two writs specially named among the rest; and that the federal courts can only issue the writ of habeas corpus, when it has become necessary to the exercise of an otherwise delegated jurisdiction; in other words, that it is subsidiary to some original process or pending suit. It is obvious, that if such had been the intention of the law-makers, it was unnecessary to name the writ of habeas corpus at all; for the simpler phrase, “all writs necessary, &c.” would in that' case have covered their meaning. But there are objections to this reading more important than any that found themselves on grammatical rules. The words that immediately follow in.the section, give the power of issuing the writ to every judge, for the purpose of inquiring into the causes of a commitment. Now, a commitment presupposes judicial action, and this action it is the object of the writ to review. Gan it be, that a single judge, sitting as such, can re-examine the causes of a detainer, which has resulted from judicial action, and is therefore prima facie a lawful one; and yet that the court, of which he is a member, cannot inquire into the causes of a detainer, made without judicial sanction, and therefore pri-ma facie unlawful? Besides, if this were the meaning of the act, it might be difficult to find the eases to which it should apply. I speak of the writ of habeas corpus ad sub-jiciendum. the great writ of personal liberty, referred to in the constitution; not that modification of it which applies specially to the case of a commitment, nor the less important forms of habeas corpus, ad responden-dum, ad faciendum, &c., which are foreign to the question. I do not remember to have met a case, either in practice or in the books, where the writ ad subjiciendum could have performed any pertinent office in a pending suit. There may be such, but they do not occur to me; and I incline very strongly to the opinion, that if the power to issue the writ of habeas corpus applies only to cases of statutory jurisdiction, outrages upon the rights of a citizen can never invoke its exercise by a federal court. If such were indeed the law of the United States, I do not see how I could escape the conclusion, that the jealousy of local interests and prejudice, which led to the constitution of federal courts, regarded only disputes about property; and that the liberty of a citizen, when beyond the state of his domicil, was not deemed worthy of equal protection. From an absurdity so gross as this, I relieve myself by repeating the words of Chief Justice Marshall, in Ex parte Watkins, 3 Pet. [28 U. S.] 201: “No law of the United States prescribes the cases in which this great writ shall be issued, nor the power of the court over the party brought up on it.” Whether, then, I look to the constitution, and its history, or to the words or the policy of the act of congress, I believe that it was meant to require of the courts of the United States, that they should dispense the privileges of the writ of habeas corpus to all parties lawfully asserting them, as other courts of similar functions and dignity had immemorially dispensed them at the common law. The congress of 17S9 made no definition of the writ, or of its conditions, or effects. They left it as the constitution left it, and as it required them to leave it, the birthright of every man within the borders of the states; like the right to air, and water, and motion, and thought, rights imprescriptible, and above all legislative discretion or caprice. And so it ought to be. There is no writ so important for good, and so little liable to be abused. At the worst, in the hands of a corrupt or ignorant judge, it may release some one from restraint who should justly have remained bound. But it deprives no one of freedom, and devests no right. It could not give to Mr. Wheeler the possession of his slaves, but it might release them from the custody of a wrong-doer. Freemen or bondsmen, they had rights; and the foremost of these was the right to have their other rights adjudicated openly and by the tribunals of the land. And this right at least, Mr. Wheeler shared with them; he also could claim a hearing.
Unless these views are incorrect through
Commitments for contempt, like the con-tempts themselves, maybe properly distributed in two classes. Either they are the punishment for an act of misconduct, or it is their object to enforce the performance of a duty. The confinement in the one case is for a fixed time, supposed to be commensurate with the offending; in the other, it is without prescribed limitation, and is determined by the willingness of the party to submit himself to the law. In the ease of Mr. Williamson, the commitment is for a refusal to answer; that is to say, to make a full and lawful answer to the writ of habeas corpus, an answer setting forth all the facts within his knowledge, which are necessary to a decision by the court, “whether he had not the power to produce the negroes, and control those in whose custody they were.” He is now undergoing restraint, not punishment. Immediately after the opinion was read, he was informed, in answer to a remark from his counsel, that the commitment was “during the contempt:” the contempt of the party and the order of the court consequent upon it, determine together.
This is all that I conceive it necessary to say of the strictly judicial action in the case. The opinions, announced by the judge upon other points, may perhaps be regarded as merely dicta. But it had appeared from the defendant’s declarations when upon the stand, that he supposed Mr. Wheeler’s slaves to have become free, and that this consideration justified his acting towards them as he had done. It seemed due to him, that the court, believing as it did those views to be incorrect, should not withhold an expression of its dissent from them. Several succinct positions were accordingly asserted by the judge: two of which may invite a few additional remarks at this time. “I know of no statute of Pennsylvania,” the judge said, “which affects to divest the rights of property of a citizen of North Carolina, acquired and asserted under the laws of that state, because he has found it needful or convenient to pass through the territory of Pennsylvania; and I am not aware that any such statute, if such -a one- were shown, could be recognized as valid in a court of the United States.” The first of these propositions may be vindicated easily. By the common law, as it came to Pennsylvania, slavery was a familiar institution. Only six days after the first legislative assembly met in Philadelphia, and thirteen days before the great charter was signed, the council was engaged in discussing a law “to prevent the escape of runaways;” and four days later, it sat judicially, William Penn himself presiding, to enforce a contract for the sale of a slave. 1 Colonial Records, 63.
This brings me to the second part of the position affirmed in the court’s opinion, namely: the right of a citizen of one state to pass freely with his slaves through the territory of another state, in which the institution of slavery is not recognized. I need not say, that before the compact of union was formed between the states, each of them was an absolutely sovereign and independent community; and that, except so far as their relations to each other and to foreign nations have been qualified by the federal constitution, each of them remain so. As such, it is bound by that great moral code, which, because of its universal obligation, is called the “law of nations.” What it could not do if freed from federative restrictions, it cannot do now: every restraint upon its policy, which duty to other states would in that case involve, binds it still, just as if the Union had been dissolved or had never been formed. All the statists unite in regarding the right of transit for person and property through the territory of a friendly state, as among those which cannot, under ordinary circumstances, be denied. Vattel, bk. 2, c. 10, §§ 132-134; Puffendorf, bk. 2, c. 3. §§ 5, 67, Ruth. Inst. bk. 2, c. 9; 1 Kent, Comm. 33, 35. It is true that the right is not an unqualified one. The state may impose reasonable conditions upon its exercise, and exact guaranties against its abuse. But subject to these limitations, it is the right of every citizen of a fpiendly state. The right is the same, and admits just the same qualifications, as to person and to property. The same argument, that denies the right of peacefully transmitting one’s property through the territories of a state, refuses the right of passage to its owner. And the question, what is to be deemed property in such a ease, refers itself necessarily to the law of the state from which the citizen brings it: a different test would sanction the confiscation of property at the will of the sovereign through whose territory it seeks to pass. If one state may decree that there shall be no property, do right of ownership in human beings; another, in a spirit of practical philanthropy only a little more energetic, may deny the protection of law to the products of slave labor; and a third may denounce a similar outlawry against all intoxicating liquids. And if the laws of a state can control the rights of property of strangers passing through its territory; then the sugar of New Orleans, the cotton of Carolina, the wines of Ohio, and the rum of New England may have their markets bounded by the states in which they are produced; and without any change of reasoning, New Jersey may refuse to citizens of Pennsylvania the right of passing along her railroads to New York. The doctrine is one that was exploded in Europe more than four hundred and fifty years ago, and finds now, or found very lately, its parting illustration in the politics of Japan. It was because, and only because, this right was acknowledged by all civilized nations, and had never been doubted among the American colonies—because each colony had at all’ times tendered its hospitalities freely to the rest, cherishing that liberal commerce which makes a brotherhood of interest even among alien states; it was because of this, that no man in the convention or country thought of making the right of transit a subject of constitutional guaranty. Everything in and about the constitution implies it, It is found in the object, “to establish a more perfect union,” in the denial to the states of the power to lay duties on imports, and .in the reservation to congress of the exclusive right to regulate commerce among the states. This last power of the general government according to the repeated and well considered decisions of the supreme court of the United States, from Gibbons v. Ogden, 9 Pet [34 U. S.] 1, to the Passenger Cases, 7 How. [48 U. S.] 283, applies to intercourse as well as navigation, to the transportation of men as well as goods, of "men who pass from state to state involuntarily, as of men who pass voluntarily; and it ex-
There was one other legal proposition affirmed in the opinion of this court, but it cannot need argument. It was, that the question, whether the negroes were or were not freed by their arrival in Pennsylvania, was irrelevant to the issue; inasmuch as whether they were freed or not, they were equally under the protection of the law, and the same obligation rested on Mr. "Williamson to make a true and full return to the writ of habeas corpus. Simple and obvious as this proposition is, it covers all the judicial action in the ease. The writ required him to produce the negroes, that the court might pass upon his legal right to carry them off or detain them. What questions might arise afterwards, or how they might be determined, was not for him to consider. His duty then, as now, was and is to bring in the bodies; or, if they had passed beyond his control, to declare under oath or affirmation, so far as he knew, what had become of them. And from this duty, or from the constraint that seeks to enforce it, there can be no escape. See the argument of Sergeant Glynn, and the remarks of Mr. Justice Gould, Wilkes’ Case, 2 Wils. 154.
The application immediately before me, hardly calls for these expanded remarks; though, rightly considered, they bear upon most of the points that were elaborated in tire argument upon the question of its reception. It purports to be a suggestion and petition from a person now in Massachusetts, who informs the court that she is one of the negroes who escaped from Mr. Wheeler, that she did so by Mr. Williamson’s counsel, and with the sanction of his presence and approval, but that he never detained her, nor has ¡my one since, and that she has never authorized an application for the writ of habeas i corpus in her behalf. Thereupon, she presents to me certain reasons, founded as she supposes in law, wherefore I ought to quash the writ heretofore issued at the relation of Mr. Wheeler. When application was made to me for leave to file this paper, I invited the learned counsel to advise me upon the question, whether I could lawfully admit the intervention of their client. My thanks are due to them for the ability and courteous bearing with which they have discussed it. But I remain unconvinced. The very name of the person who authenticates the paper is a stranger to any proceeding that is or has been before me.
Upon the reading of the above opinion. Mr. Cadwalader, as a member of the bar of the court not counsel or attorney in the original or subsequent proceedings, asked leave as amicus curiae to suggest that, in the opinion of the court, an incident of the original proceeding, which has been publicly misrepresented, was not noticed. “It has been publicly reported,” Mr. Cadwalader said, “that after the opinion of the court, which resulted in Mr. Williamson’s commitment, had been read, his counsel applied to the court for leave to amend his return, which leave was refused. The present suggestion is made under the belief of the member of the bar who makes it, that this report was erroneous, and that what occurred was as follows. When the opinion in the original proceeding was read, the counsel of Mr. Williamson asked if a motion to amend the return would be received. and the court replied, that the motion must be reduced to writing, and that it could not be received until the court’s order should be filed with the clerk and recorded; adding that the court would then receive any motion which the counsel for Mr. Williamson might desire to make. The court’s order was then filed by the clerk, and entered on record; but no motion to amend was then or afterwards made, although the court paused to give an opportunity for making it, and invited the counsel then or afterwards, to make any motion which their client might be advised to make.”
KANE, District Judge, said: The recollections of Mr. Cadwalader concur substantially with my own. There certainly was no motion made by the counsel of Mr. Williamson, for leave to amend his return. A wish was expressed to make such a motion, and the judge asked that the motion might be reduced to writing and filed. But the motion was not drawn out or presented for the court’s consideration, and the court never expressed any purpose to overrule such a motion, if one should be presented.
“At a council, held at Philadelphia, ye 29th 1st mo., 1683. Present. William Penn, proprietary, and governor of Pennsylvania and. counties annexed, Thos. Holmes, John Richardson, William Clarke, John Simcox, James Harrison, (and eight others.) The petition of Nathaniel Allen was read, shewing that he had sould a servant to Henry Bowman, for six hundred weight of bee'fe, with ye hide and tallow, and six pounds sterling, which ye said Bowman delayed to pay ye said petitioner, showing likewise that ye said Henry Bowman and Walter Humphrey hired a boat of the said petitioner only for one month, and kept the same boat 18 weeks from the petitioner to his great prejudice: Then it was ordered, that William Clarke, John Sim-cox and James Harrison should speak to Henry Bowman concerning this matter.”—Page 62. The great charter was signed by William Penn,
Neither the petition for the writ of habeas corpus, nor the writ itself, names Jane Johnson.
“Interdiction omnibus competit—Nemo enim prohibendus est libertati favere.”—Dig. bk. 46, tit. 20, § 9.