70 Ohio St. 2d 182 | Ohio | 1982
The question before the court in the instant appeal is whether appellee is entitled to a new trial at which he may present expert psychiatric testimony relating to his alleged incapacity to form the requisite specific intent to commit aggravated murder and aggravated burglary. The state, finding support in the dissent below, contends that “all relevant admissible evidence related to the mental status of Moses Wilcox was before the jury.” As a consequence thereof,
The parties herein and the court below, relied on State v. Nichols (1965), 3 Ohio App. 2d 183, as authority for the proposition that the partial defense of diminished capacity is recognized in Ohio. The case of State v. Jackson (1972), 32 Ohio St. 2d 203, certiorari denied (1973), 411 U. S. 909, has gone unnoticed, or at the very least uncited, at any stage of these proceedings. In Jackson the question of whether Ohio would recognize the diminished capacity defense was briefed, argued, and explicitly, albeit cursorily, rejected by this court.
I.
At the outset we note that there are a number of variations on the diminished capacity theme and a variety of labels have been applied to the doctrine.
The diminished capacity defense originated in Scotland more than a century ago “to reduce the punishment of the ‘partially insane’ from murder to culpable homicide, a non-capital offense. See HM Advocate v. Dingwall, [1867] J. C. 466.” Arenella, supra, at page 830, fn. 16. The doctrine has been widely accepted overseas, see Arenella, supra, and Comment, Criminal Law — Partial Insanity — Evidentiary Relevance Defined, 16 Rutgers L. Rev. 174, 176-77, fn. 8, but most American jurisdictions, with the notable exception of California,
The diminished capacity defense developed as a covert judicial response to perceived inequities in the criminal law. The purported justifications for the doctrine include the following:
“(1) it ameliorates defects in a jurisdiction’s insanity test criteria; (2) it permits the jury to avoid imposing the death penalty on mentally disabled killers who are criminally responsible for their acts; and (3) it permits the jury to make more accurate individualized culpability judgments.” Arenella, supra, at page 853.
In addition the diminished capacity defense has a certain logical appeal when juxtaposed against the settled rule that evidence of voluntary intoxication may be considered in determining whether an accused acted with the requisite specific intent. See State v. Fox (1981), 68 Ohio St. 2d 53. The analogy to the partial defense of voluntary intoxication figured prominently in the Brawner court’s analysis. The court stated:
“Neither logic nor justice can tolerate a jurisprudence that defines the elements of an offense as requiring a mental state such that one defendant can properly argue that his voluntary*187 drunkenness removed his capacity to form the specific intent but another defendant is inhibited from a submission of his contention that an abnormal mental condition, for which he was in no way responsible, negated his capacity to form a particular specific intent, even though the condition did not exonerate him from all criminal responsibility.” 471 F. 2d at page 999. Cf. Wells, supra, at page 357; Gorshen, supra, at pages 727-28. See, also, Lewin, supra, at page 1092, and Weihofen and Overholser, Mental Disorder Affecting the Degree of a Crime, 56 Yale L. J. 959, 962-963 (hereinafter “Weihofen”).
Upon examination, however, we find none of the foregoing justifications for the defense of diminished capacity sufficiently compelling as to warrant its adoption, particularly in light of the problems posed by the doctrine, problems even its proponents acknowledge.
I A.
The diminished capacity defense does serve to ameliorate the limitations of the traditional, M’Naghten,
“Efforts to ‘get around’ the M’Naghten rule were undertaken in New Hampshire as long ago as 1870 (State v. Pike, 49*188 N.H. 399, 429), by Judge Bazelon in 1954 in Durham v. United States, 214 F. 2d 862, by Chief Judge Biggs of the Third Circuit in United States v. Currens (1961) 290 F. 2d 751, 774, and by this court when in 1949 we adopted a significant variation of M’Naghten in People v. Wells (1949) 33 Cal. 2d 330, a thoughtful concept developed by Justice Schauer, and further explicated in People v. Gorshen (1959) 51 Cal. 2d 716.
“* * * [I]n People v. Henderson (1963) 60 Cal. 2d 482, 490, Justice Traynor frankly conceded the Wells-Gorshen ‘purpose and effect are to ameliorate the law governing criminal responsibility prescribed by the M’Naghten rule,’ * * *."
The ameliorative argument loses much of its force, however, in jurisdictions that have abandoned or expanded upon the narrow M’Naghten standard. The test for insanity in Ohio is set forth in State v. Staten (1969), 18 Ohio St. 2d 13, paragraph one of the syllabus, as follows:
“One accused of criminal conduct is not responsible for such criminal conduct if, at the time of such conduct, as a result of mental disease or defect, he does not have the capacity either to know the wrongfulness of his conduct or to conform his conduct to the requirements of law. * * *” (Citations omitted.)
While this standard is arguably less expansive than that espoused by the drafters of the Model Penal Code, see Section 4.01,
“* * * ‘partial responsibility’ becomes an important alternative to the plea of insanity, particularly when the question of capital punishment is removed. The defendant facing a murder charge must then choose between, on the one hand, insanity and indeterminate commitment and, on the other, conviction and a long sentence, which may be reduced by parole. Some indication of how they choose is afforded by the recent English experience with ‘diminished responsibility.’ That plea has become so popular that it threatens to displace the insanity defense entirely.” Goldstein, supra, at pages 195-196.
Professor Arenella notes that “[sjeriously disturbed defendants can avoid an indefinite commitment to a mental hospital for the criminally insane by relying on the diminished responsibility defense which frequently leads to a reduced term in prison.” Arenella, supra, at page 854. According to this view, the principal practical effect of the diminished capacity defense is to enable mentally ill offenders to receive shorter and more certain sentences than they would receive if they were adjudged insane. Having satisfied ourselves that Ohio’s test for criminal responsibility adequately safeguards the rights of the insane, we are disinclined to adopt an alternative defense that could swallow up the insanity defense and its attendant commitment provisions. See R. C. 2945.40.
We can quickly dispose of the argument that the diminished capacity defense alleviates the harshness of the death penalty when mentally ill but nonetheless sane defendants are convicted of capital crimes.
IC.
The justifications for diminished capacity relating to the defense’s potential for more accurate, individualized culpability judgments and its logical relevance are based largely on analogies to the insanity defense and the defense of intoxication, respectively. These arguments were discussed at some length in Bethea v. United States (D. C. App. 1976), 365 A. 2d
“Our principal objection to the Brawner dicta is its apparent abandonment of traditional legal theory. The essence of the diminished capacity concept embraced in that decision is that the circumstance of mental deficiency should not be confined to use as an all-or-nothing defense. * * * It is true, of course, that the existence of the required state of mind is to be determined subjectively in the sense that the issue must be resolved according to the particular circumstances of a given case. However, this fact may not be allowed to obscure the critical difference between the legal concepts of mens rea and insanity. * * * The former refers to the existence in fact of a ‘guilty mind’; insanity, on the other hand, connotes a presumption that a particular individual lacks the capacity to possess such a state of mind. It is upon this distinction that the ‘logic’ of the diminished capacity doctrine founders. * * * The concept of insanity is simply a device the law employs to define the outer limits of that segment of the general population to whom these presumptions concerning the capacity for criminal intent shall not be applied. The line between the sane and the insane for the purposes of criminal adjudication is not drawn because for one group the actual existence of the necessary mental state (or lack thereof) can be determined with any greater certainty, but rather because those whom the law declares insane are demonstrably so aberrational in their psychiatric characteristics that we choose to make the assumption that they are incapable of possessing the specified state of mind. Within the*192 range of individuals who are not ‘insane,’ the law does not recognize the readily demonstrable fact that as between individual criminal defendants the nature and development of their mental capabilities may vary greatly.”
In the same vein as Bethea, the Wisconsin Supreme Court in Steele v. State (1979), 97 Wis. 2d 72, 294 N.W. 2d 2, recently made the following pertinent observations:
“* * * The determination of capacity to form an intent — to find whether or not the alleged offender intended to do, in the sense of the criminal law, what he in fact did — requires a fine tuning of an entirely different nature than that required for the admission of evidence on the general question of insanity for the determination of whether or not there should be criminal responsibility * * *. To make * * * [the insanity] determination requires no fine tuning. It is, rather, a gross evaluation that a person’s conduct and mental state is so beyond the limits of accepted norms that to hold him criminally responsible would be unjust. This is a far cry from accepting testimony which purports to prove or disprove a specific intent, as distinguished from criminal responsibility. While some courts may have blind faith in all phases of psychiatry, this court does not. There is substantial doubt whether evidence such as was sought to be introduced here is scientifically sound, and there is substantial legal doubt that it is probative on the point for which it was asserted in this case.” Id. at pages 96-97.14
Theoretically the insanity concept operates as a bright line test separating the criminally responsible from the criminally irresponsible.
The Brawner court emphasized the apparent illogic of permitting evidence of voluntary intoxication to be introduced to negate specific intent while precluding the introduction of evidence of an abnormal mental condition not amounting to insanity for the same purpose. While we concede that there is a superficial attractiveness to the intoxication-diminished capacity analogy, upon closer examination we, like the court in Bethea, find the concepts to be quite disparate. The Bethea
“The rule that evidence of intoxication may be employed to demonstrate the absence of specific intent figured prominently in the Brawner court’s advocacy of consistency in the treatment of expert evidence of mental impairment. The asserted analogy is flawed, however, by the fact that there are significant evidentiary distinctions between psychiatric abnormality and the recognized incapacitating circumstances. Unlike the notion of partial or relative insanity, conditions such as intoxication, medication, epilepsy, infancy, or senility are, in varying degrees, susceptible to quantification or objective demonstration, and to lay understanding. As the Ninth Circuit observed in Wahrlich v. Arizona, 479 F. 2d 1137, 1138 (9th Cir.), certiorari denied, 414 U. S. 1011, 94 S. Ct. 375, 38 L. Ed. 2d 249 (1973):
“ ‘Exposure to the effects of age and of intoxicants upon state of mind is a part of common human experience which fact finders can understand and apply; indeed, they would apply them even if the state did not tell them they could. The esoterics of psychiatry are not within the ordinary ken.’ ”
It takes no great expertise for jurors to determine whether an accused was “ ‘so intoxicated as to be mentally unable to intend anything.(unconscious),’ ” Jackson, supra, at page 206, whereas the ability to assimilate and apply the finely differentiated psychiatric concepts associated with diminished capacity demands a sophistication (or as critics would maintain a sophistic bent) that jurors (and officers of the court) ordinarily have not developed. We are convinced as was the Bethea court, that these “significant evidentiary distinctions” preclude treating diminished capacity and voluntary intoxication as functional equivalents for purposes of partial exculpation from criminal responsibility.
We have examined the commonly asserted justifications for diminished capacity and have found them wanting. We have also looked at the leading California cases,
Commentators, including proponents as well as opponents of diminished capacity, attempted to untangle the several strands of the California diminished capacity defense. Their conclusions are not overly heartening. See, e.g., Fingarette & Haase, Mental Disabilities and Criminal Responsibility 117-133 (hereinafter “Fingarette”) (“To have a variety of such diminished capacity formulas, arbitrarily shifting and even inconsistent with one another, as is the case at present, is unsatisfactory law,” id. at 131); Arenella, supra, at pages 836-849 (”[D]octrinal morass * * * results from * * * [California] court’s perpetration of the legal fiction that diminished capacity testimony can be correlated to different statutory state of mind requirements,” id. at 848); Lewin, supra, at pages 1077-1089 and 1092-1096 (“The courts adopting the California doctrine have been unable to provide meaningful standards to guide the courts in assessing the quality and quantum of psychiatric evidence necessary to carry the defense. As a result there is no clear definition of the doctrine and no clear statement of the mental deficiency necessary to support the defense,” id. at 1093); Comment, 18 U.C.L.A. L. Rev. supra, at pages 567-572 (“The inconsistent application of the [diminished capacity] defense, by which defendants in similar factual situations receive substantially different treatments, frustrates the criminal law’s attempt to achieve equal treatment for all defendants similarly situated,” id. at 570); Comment, 60 Cal. L. Rev., supra; Note, Restricting the Admission of Psychiatric Testimony on a Defendant’s Mental State: Wisconsin’s Steele Curtain, 1981 Wis. L. Rev. 733, 774-780 (“While the California experience indicates the pressures which exist to expand, the range of relevant psychiatric testimony in the guilty determination process, the
The upshot of the doctrinal confusion and the public outcry over cases like People v. White, supra, finally prompted the California legislature to abolish the diminished capacity defense by statute. See West’s Anno. Cal. Penal Code Section 28 (1982 Supp.); West’s Cal. Leg. Service 1981, Chapter 404, at page 1201, Section 4. Thus the diminished capacity concept has been repudiated in the very jurisdiction that formerly gave the greatest credence to the doctrine.
The open-endedness of the diminished capacity doctrine troubles us as well. Under the California rule evidence of diminished capacity could only be introduced to negate the mental element in crimes requiring specific intent. The specific intent limitation imposed by the California courts did not, however, flow from the theory underlying the diminished capacity doctrine and, indeed, may have been in direct conflict therewith.
*197 “The Brawner court did indicate that for the time being the admission of psychiatric evidence of diminished capacity would be limited to the trial of offenses involving specific intent. * * * We are not satisfied that the rule could be confined to easily. Assuming the competency of experts to testify as to an accused’s capacity for specific intent we see no logical bar to their observations as to the possible existence or lack of malice or general intent. Moreover, it does not appear to us that the balance between the evidentiary value of medical testimony and its potential for improper impact upon the trier would very sufficiently as between the various degrees of mens rea to warrant such an artificial distinction.” (Citation omitted.) If however, in the interests of doctrinal purity evidence of diminished capacity were admitted to disprove the mental element in general intent crimes, then “successful application of the diminished capacity doctrine * * * would create the anomalous result of a ‘partial defense’ leading to outright acquittal of the defendant because of the absence of a lesser included offense.” Arenella, supra, at page 832, fn. 25. This “anomalous result,” although a theoretical possibility is unlikely to be countenanced by courts because “[t]he complete acquittal of such offenders would release from state control the very persons society should probably fear most — because their endowments are fewer, because they are more suggestible, more manipulable, more fearful.” Goldstein, supra, at page 202. Nevertheless, the potential applicability of diminished capacity as a complete defense to crimes of general intent dramatically highlights the paradox inhering in the doctrine:
“The subjective [diminished capacity] theory classes as less serious the offender who is less culpable; assuming him to be less ‘guilty,’ it proceeds to class him as less dangerous and either reduces the length of time he may be detained or releases him entirely. Yet his objective behavior may mark him as extremely dangerous and seriously in need not only of correction and treatment but of detention as well.” Id. This paradox did not escape notice in Bethea, wherein the court quoted the pre-Braumer case of Fisher v. United States (C. A. D. C. 1945), 149 F. 2d 28, affirmed 328 U. S. 463 (1946), for the proposition that “ ‘it is obvious that brutal murders are*198 not committed by normal people. To give [such] an instruction * * * is to tell the jury that they are at liberty to acquit one who commits a brutal crime because he has the abnormal tendencies of persons capable of such crimes.’ ” Bethea, supra, at page 85, quoting Fisher, supra, at page 29. Under a diminished capacity regime, however, the more brutal, bizarre, or sensational the crime, the greater is the likelihood of a successful diminished capacity defense.19 “Psychiatry’s elastic definitions of mental abnormality easily encompass anyone who kills another human being without justification or excuse because such an act demonstrates a serious deviation from cultural and social norms. From such abnormality, the expert can readily infer that the accused had extreme difficulty in obeying the law and is therefore entitled to formal mitigation.” Arenella, supra, at page 858. In other words, the commission of the offense in most instances becomes ipso facto evidence of diminished capacity.
“While there may be superficial appeal to the idea that the standards of criminal responsibility should be applied as subjectively as possible, the overriding danger of the disputed doctrine is that it would discard the traditional presumptions concerning mens rea without providing for a corresponding adjustment in the means whereby society is enabled to protect itself from those who cannot or will not conform their conduct to the requirements of the law. Bethea supra, at page 90. Thus, the effect of adopting a diminished capacity model transcends the doctrine’s potential to transform criminal trials into psychiatric shouting matches. Rather, the diminished capacity theory forcefully challenges conventional concepts of culpability and “involvefs] a fundamental change in the common law theory of responsibility.” Fisher, supra, 328 U. S. at 476. Echoing Bethea, “[w]e conclude that the potential impact of concepts such as diminished capacity or partial insanity — however labeled — is of a scope and magnitude which*199 precludes their proper adoption by an expedient modification of the rules of evidence. If such principles are to be incorporated into our law of criminal responsibility, the change should lie within the province of the legislature.” Bethea supra, at page 92. See Fisher, supra, 328 U. S. at page 476.
We hold, therefore, that the partial defense of diminished capacity is not recognized in Ohio (State v. Jackson, supra [32 Ohio St. 2d 203], followed) and consequently, a defendant may not offer expert psychiatric testimony, unrelated to the insanity defense, to show that the defendant lacked the mental capacity to form the specific mental state required for a particular crime or degree of crime.
For the reasons hereinbefore stated, the judgment of the Court of Appeals is reversed.
Judgment reversed.
The state also raises an issue relating to Crim. R. 16, which we need not reach.
Jackson sub silentio limited Pigman v. State (1846), 14 Ohio 555, to its facts and rejected Pigman dicta that arguably would support the admission of evidence of diminished capacity.
The various names include inter alia diminished or partial responsibility, partial insanity, and the Wells-Gorshen rule (after People v. Wells [1949], 33 Cal. 2d 330, 202 P. 2d 53, certiorari denied 338 U. S. 836, and People v. Gorshen [1959], 51 Cal. 2d 716, 336 P. 2d 492). Commentators have fashioned a functionally related nomenclature that seeks to differentiate the ways in which the doctrine has been applied. See, e.g., Arenella, The Diminished Capacity and Diminished Responsibility Defenses: Two Children of a Doomed Marriage, 77 Colum. L. Rev. 827 (hereinafter “Arenella”) (distinguishing the "mens rea model,” “diminished capacity,” and “diminished respon
See, e.g., Wells, supra; Gorshen, supra; People v. Conley (1966), 64 Cal. 2d 310, 411 P. 2d 911; People v. Wolff 61 Cal. 2d 795, 394 P. 2d 959. But, see, West’s Anno. Cal. Penal Code Section 28 (1982 Supp.); West’s Cal. Leg. Service 1981, Chapter 404 at page 1201, Section 4.
The Brawner court included Ohio as a diminished capacity jurisdiction, citing Nichols, supra, but erroneously attributed the Nichols decision to the state’s “highest court.” 471 P. 2d at page 1000.
See, e.g., Diamond, Criminal Responsibility of the Mentally Ill, 14 Stan. L. Rev. 59, 82-86 (hereinafter “Diamond”); Diamond, From Durham to Brawner, A Futile Journey, 1973 Wash. Univ. L. Q. 109, (hereinafter “Futile Journey”), Lewin, supra, 1089-1097; Note, A Punishment Rationale for Diminished Capacity, 18 U.C.L.A. L. Rev. 561, 570-572; Note, Keeping Wolff From the Door: California’s Diminished Capacity Concept, 60 Cal. L. Rev. 1641, 1653-1655.
M’Naghten’s Case (H.L. 1843), 10 C. & F. 200, 8 Eng. Rep. 718.
See, e.g., Wells, supra, at pages 352-354, and cases cited therein. The California Supreme Court abandoned its M’Naghten test in People v. Drew (1978), 22 Cal. 3d 333, 583 P. 2d 1318, and adopted the American Law Institute standard (Model Penal Code Section 4.01). See, also, Arenella, supra, at pages 854-855; Comment, The Diminished Capacity Defense in California; An Idea Whose Time Has Gone? 3 Glendale L. Rev. 311, 318.
Model Penal Code Section 4.01(1) states:
“A person is not responsible for criminal conduct if at the time of such conduct as a result of mental disease or defect he lacks substantial capacity either to appreciate the criminality [wrongfulness] of his conduct or to conform his conduct to the requirements of law.”
In Staten, supra, at page 15, this court specifically acknowledged that the Ohio insanity rule is broader than M’Naghten. Staten also prefigured, at page 20, our diminished capacity ruling in Jackson.
See, e.g., Model Penal Code Section 4.02(2) and Comment 2, Tentative Draft No. 4, at page 193.
The court has spoken with many voices in the death penalty cases that have come before it in the last decade or so. What seems to be required as a minimum before capital punishment may be imposed are clear standards and a full consideration of mitigating factors so as to provide a “meaningful basis for distinguishing the few cases in which it [capital punishment] is imposed from the many cases in which it is not.” Furman v. Georgia (1972), 408 U. S. 238, 313 (White, J., concurring). See, also, Gregg v. Georgia (1976), 428 U. S. 153; Proffitt v. Florida, (1976), 428 U. S. 242; Jurek v. Texas (1976), 428 U. S. 262; Woodson v. North Carolina (1976), 428 U. S. 280; Roberts v. Louisiana (1976), 428 U. S. 325; Lockett v. Ohio (1978), 438 U. S. 586; Beck v. Alabama (1980), 447 U. S. 625.
“Prior to 1971, the federal courts in the District of Columbia were authoritative expositors of local as well as federal law, * * *. The situation changed radically when, in the early 1970’s, Congress restructured the District of Columbia courts [District of Columbia Court Reorganization Act of 1970, Pub. L. No. 91-358, Title I, Section 111, 84 Stat. 475 (1973)], and reposed in them full responsibility for the development of the District’s own law. From then onward, the relationship of the federal to the local judiciary was to be akin to that historically existent in the states.” Steorts v. American Airlines (C. A. D. C. 1981), 647 F. 2d 194, 196.
Steele, moreover, represented a turnabout in Wisconsin law as the court overturned its prior decision in Schimmel v. State (1978), 84 Wis. 2d 287, 267 N.W. 2d 271, insofar as Schimmel had permitted the introduction of psychiatric evidence during the guilt phase of Wisconsin’s bifurcated trial system.
That the legal theory of insanity does not necessarily square with psychiatric concepts of mental illness is a point that has been frequently recognized and is the source of a good deal of the criticism aimed at the insanity defense. See, e.g., Diamond, supra, at page 62 (“Central to the difficulties with any definition of legal insanity is the all-or-none conceptualization of the law. A defendant is either sane and totally responsible, or insane, and not at all responsible. Such all-or-none concepts are peculiarly foreign to modern psychiatric thinking. Neither normal persons nor mentally disturbed persons are ever ‘all-or-none’ in their psychological functioning”), and at page
Cf. Diamond, supra, at page 73:
“If, * * * there are innumerable kinds of mentes reae, then. I would assert that there must exist innumerable degrees of any particular mens rea. We thus arrive at a legal spectrum of an infinitely graduated scale of responsibility which corresponds, or could be made to correspond closely, to -the psychological reality of human beings as understood by twentieth century medical psychology.”
See, e.g., cases cited in fn. 4, supra.
See, e.g., Fingarette, supra, at pages 129-130; Arenella, supra, at page 832, fn. 25; Weihofen, supra, at pages 977-978. Cf. Diamond, supra, at page 83:
“The next step * * * is to expand the principle of limited or diminished responsibility of the mentally ill offender to include all definitions of crime. It was easier to introduce this principle in the crimes of homicide because there already existed the legal structure of graduated responsibility for homicide. But when the courts, and particularly the public, get used to the idea of giving full consideration to the mental and emotional abnormalities of the homicide offender, there will be little difficulty in having the same principles and practices applied to all crimes.”
Arguably this was the California experience with the diminished capacity defense. See, e.g., People v. Wolff, supra; People v. Goedecke (1967), 65 Cal. 2d 850, 423 P. 2d 777; People v. Nicolaus (1967), 65 Cal. 2d 866, 423 P. 2d 787; People v. Bassett (1968), 69 Cal. 2d 122, 443 P. 2d 777 (brutal murders reduced in degree pursuant to California’s diminished capacity rule). But, see, People v. Sirhan (1972), 7 Cal. 3d 710, 497 P. 2d 1121.