876 F.2d 902 | D.C. Cir. | 1989
Lead Opinion
Opinion PER CURIAM.
Separate Opinions filed by Circuit Judge SILBERMAN and Senior Circuit Judge MacKINNON.
Dissenting Opinion filed by Chief Judge WALD.
The opinions by Judges Silberman and MacKinnon in some respects differ in analysis. However, both conclude that the FCC’s minority distress sale program unconstitutionally deprives Alan Shurberg and Shurberg Broadcasting of their equal protection rights under the Fifth Amendment because the program is not narrowly tailored to remedy past discrimination or to promote programming diversity. Specifically, the program unduly burdens Shur-berg, an innocent nonminority, and is not
The cause is remanded to the Federal Communications Commission for further proceedings not inconsistent with this opinion.
Judgment accordingly.
Alan Shurberg, a long-time resident of the Hartford, Connecticut area, and Shur-berg Broadcasting Company of Hartford, Inc., have been trying since 1982 to replace Faith Center, Inc., as the licensee of Channel 18 in Hartford. Shurberg appeals from an FCC Memorandum Opinion and Order granting Faith Center permission to sell its broadcast properties to a minority-controlled enterprise pursuant to the Commission’s distress sale policy. After Faith Center’s second unsuccessful attempt at a distress sale, Shurberg sought to file with the FCC a construction application that was mutually exclusive of Faith Center’s renewal application and to have his application set for comparative hearing with Faith Center’s renewal application. As the FCC could grant either Shurberg’s request for comparative consideration or Faith Center’s petition for permission to assign its broadcast license to a third distress sale buyer — intervenor Astroline Communications Company Limited Partnership (“As-troline”) — but not both, the FCC considered the two requests together. Deciding in favor of Faith Center, the FCC gave slightly greater weight to its distress sale policy than to the statutory policy favoring competition in licensing. Faith Center, Inc., 99 F.C.C.2d 1164, 1170 (1984). The Commission also held that the racial preference embodied in the distress sale policy did not violate the Constitution because the policy was meant to remedy past discrimination and to promote diversity of ownership and programming. Id. at 1170-72. And the Commission sustained the bona fides of Astroline’s minority status, dismissing Shurberg’s contention that Astroline’s purported minority ownership was a sham. Id. at 1172-73.
Our resolution of Shurberg’s appeal in this matter has been delayed for some time. After oral argument in this case, developments in a related case, Steele v. FCC, 770 F.2d 1192 (D.C.Cir.1985), led us to ask the FCC if it still fully supported the constitutionality of its distress sale policy. The Commission acknowledged that it had doubts and requested that we remand in order for it to reconsider the matter fully. In the midst of that reexamination, however, Congress passed and the President signed a continuing resolution forbidding, inter alia, the expenditure of funds for reconsideration of the distress sale policy. The Commission promptly terminated its proceedings and reinstated the policy, and therefore we must now consider Shur-berg’s challenges.
Shurberg argues that: the FCC’s decision is inconsistent with the governing statute, regulations, and judicial precedents, which he asserts required the Commission to consider his competitive application; the FCC’s proceedings were marred by ex parte contacts and other irregularities; the distress sale policy unconstitutionally discriminated against him on the basis of race. I discern no substantive or procedural flaw in the FCC’s action in this case that would require reversal if the agency’s distress sale policy were constitutional. I nevertheless vote to overturn the Commission’s decision because I have concluded, for the reasons set forth below, that the distress sale policy, as applied to bar Shurberg’s opportunity to compete for the license, is unconstitutional.
I.
A.
As a general rule, a licensee whose qualifications to hold a broadcast license come into question may not assign or transfer that license until the FCC has resolved its doubts in a noncomparative hearing. This policy is premised on the notion that “a licensee ... has nothing to assign or transfer unless and until he has established his own qualifications_” Northland Television, Inc., 42 Rad.Reg.2d (P & F) 1107, 1110 (1978); see also Jefferson Radio Co.
In 1978, the FCC expanded the applicability of the distress sale policy. It would continue to be available “in circumstances similar to those now obtaining,” but, in addition,
in order to further encourage broadcasters to seek out minority purchasers, [the FCC would] permit licensees whose licenses have been designated for revocation hearing, or whose renewal applications have been designated for hearing on basic qualification issues ... to transfer or assign their licenses at a “distress sale” price to applicants with a significant minority ownership interest, assuming the proposed assignee or transferee meets our other qualifications.
1978 Policy Statement, 68 F.C.C.2d at 983 (footnote omitted). A holder whose license the FCC indicated it might terminate or refuse to renew due to basic qualification issues would be eligible, with FCC approval, to sell its assets and transfer its license to a qualified minority enterprise.
B.
This case has a long and complicated procedural history that reaches back to a period before the proceedings on Faith Center’s Hartford license and forward beyond the time of oral argument here. In addition to the Hartford license, Faith Center also held broadcast licenses for three California stations. In 1978, the FCC designated Faith Center’s renewal application for its San Bernardino station for hearing because of allegations of fraud in Faith Center’s over-the-air solicitation for funds and failure to cooperate with an FCC investigation. In 1980, the Administrative Law Judge in the San Bernardino proceeding dismissed Faith Center’s renewal application because of Faith Center’s refusal to cooperate in the proceeding. The Commission affirmed that decision, as did this court. Faith Center, Inc., 82 F.C.C.2d 1 (1980), reconsid. denied, FCC 81-235 (1981), aff'd mem., Faith Center, Inc. v. FCC, 679 F.2d 261 (1982), cert. denied, 459
In December 1980, the FCC designated Faith Center’s renewal application for its WHCT-TV Channel 18 license in Hartford for noncomparative hearing. Faith Center had filed a renewal application in 1977, but it had been held in deferred status pending the outcome of the San Bernardino proceedings. After the San Bernardino proceedings were dismissed, the FCC reactivated the Hartford proceedings to consider issues left unresolved in the San Bernardi-no proceedings. The FCC’s order reactivating the Hartford proceedings acknowledged Faith Center’s interest in making a distress sale, which it could do while its application was in designated-for-hearing status, but not while in deferred status.
Faith Center filed with the FCC, in February 1981, a petition for special relief requesting permission to make a distress sale to Television Corp. of Hartford. The FCC granted the petition and the renewal application on condition that the proposed as-signee be “found fully qualified ... and that the contemplated assignment is in fact consummated within 90 days following such determination.” Faith Center, Inc., 88 F.C.C.2d 788, 795 (1981). The FCC’s order further stated, “[s]hould either condition not occur, this proceeding will return to its status prior to the filing of the above described Petition for Special Relief.” Id. The proposed sale to Television Corp., however, was not consummated, and the application was withdrawn. On September 29, 1982, Faith Center again petitioned for special relief, seeking approval for a distress sale to Interstate Media Corp. The FCC again granted Faith Center’s petition and application — this time over the opposition of Shurberg and others — and again conditioned its approval upon the proposed as-signee’s being found fully qualified and upon the sale’s being consummated within ninety days of the qualification determination. If either of these conditions failed, the application was to revert to its prior designated-for-hearing status.
Shurberg, on December 1, 1983, filed an application for a construction permit to build a television station in Hartford, an application that would be mutually exclusive with the Channel 18 renewal application. The FCC rejected this filing on the ground that its regulations precluded it from accepting applications in competition with designated-for-hearing renewal applications until the resolution of the noncom-parative proceedings. See 47 C.F.R. § 73.3516(e) (1987); City of Angels Broadcasting v. FCC, 745 F.2d 656, 662-64 (D.C.Cir.1984).
In February and April of 1984, Faith Center and Interstate Media informed the FCC they could not consummate the proposed distress sale. Faith Center said, however, that it had “an excellent opportunity to consummate an assignment to other minority parties,” and it requested another chance to pursue a distress sale. Letter from Kenneth E. Robertson (Counsel for Faith Center) to Allan Glasser (FCC Mass Media Bureau), March 29,1984. Faith Center’s renewal application reverted to designated-for-hearing status, and the ALT scheduled a prehearing conference. On April 19, 1984, Shurberg in turn filed a petition for extraordinary relief requesting that the construction permit application he had attempted to file in December 1983 be designated for comparative hearing with Faith Center’s renewal application. Then on June 25,1984, before the FCC had acted on Shurberg’s petition, Faith Center petitioned the Commission for approval of a distress sale to Astroline. The FCC’s General Counsel solicited comments from all parties on the conflicting requests for relief. Astroline, the Department of Communications of the Capital Region Conference of Churches, and the FCC’s Mass Media Bureau submitted comments in favor of the distress sale; Shurberg recorded his opposition to the sale and urged his application be set for comparative hearing.
The Commission announced its decision on the petitions for relief in a Memorandum Opinion and Order released December 7, 1984. Faith Center, Inc., 99 F.C.C.2d 1164. It first addressed Shurberg’s argument that he was entitled to a comparative hearing against Faith Center’s renewal application because the FCC’s September
Shurberg’s argument that the distress sale policy violated his constitutional right to equal protection was rejected by the Commission as “without merit.” In reaching that conclusion, the FCC relied both on its findings of “underrepresentation” of minorities in the broadcast industry and its view that increased minority ownership would increase programming diversity. Id. at 1170-71. The Commission also drew support from the 1982 amendments to the Communications Act in which Congress had approved the use of a lottery system that incorporated significant preferences for minority applicants as an alternative to the comparative hearing process. Id. at 1171-72. The conference report accompanying those amendments contained a statement that “the effects of past inequities stemming from racial and ethnic discrimination have resulted in a severe underrep-resentation of minorities in the media of mass communications, as it has adversely affected their participation in other sectors of the economy as well.” H.R.Rep. No. 765, 97th Cong., 2d Sess. 43 (1982) U.S. Code Cong. & Admin.News 1982 pp. 2237, 2281. Noting that the conference report also referred to the FCC’s 1978 policy statement, which expanded the distress sale policy, in establishing the need for preferential treatment of minorities, the Commission reasoned that “Congress ... has recognized the need for and approved the implementation of the minority ownership policies set forth in the 1978 policy statement.” 99 F.C.C.2d at 1172.
Shurberg also failed in his attack based on Astroline’s qualifications as a bona fide minority to participate in a distress sale. The Astroline partnership had two general partners and one limited partner. Richard P. Ramirez, the general partner whose Hispanic surname was the predicate for Astro-line’s participation in the distress sale as a minority enterprise, held a twenty-one percent ownership interest and a seventy percent voting interest in the partnership. WHCT Management, Inc., the second general partner, held a nine percent ownership interest and a thirty percent voting interest. Astroline Co. — not to be confused with the Astroline partnership — owned the remaining seventy percent of the company. The Astroline partnership represented to the FCC that the general partners would control the partnership’s affairs and would vote in accordance with their respective partnership interests. Shurberg attacked the bona fides of this arrangement, pointing to records indicating Ramirez had contributed less than one percent of the station’s operating capital; Shurberg asserted it was patently incredible that such a small contributor would be given control of the enterprise. Shurberg alleged that Ramirez was included in the partnership only as a device to permit the real party in interest, Astroline Co., to participate in the distress sale. The Commission determined, however, the Astroline partnership satisfied the basic requirements of minority control. Id. at 1173.
Shurberg filed this petition for review.
In light of these developments, we asked the FCC to file a supplemental brief in this case clarifying its position on the constitutionality of the minority distress sale provision. Instead of filing a brief, the Commission responded that the “distress sale policy raises many of the same questions that are present in the Steele case,” and requested a remand to allow inquiry into the distress sale policy along with consideration of the comparative preference policies raised in Steele. We granted the motion and remanded the record in June 1987.
On December 22, 1987, the President signed into law a continuing resolution appropriating funds for the federal government for fiscal year 1988. Pub.L. No. 100-202, 101 Stat. 1329 (1987). Among its provisions was the following:
That none of the funds appropriated by this Act shall be used to repeal, to retroactively apply changes in, or to continue a reexamination of, the policies of the Federal Communications Commission with respect to comparative licensing, distress sales and tax certificates granted under 26 U.S.C. 1071, to expand minority and women ownership of broadcasting licenses, including those established in Statement of Policy on Minority Ownership of Broadcast Facilities, 68 F.C.C.2d 979 and 69 F.C.C.2d 1591, as amended 52 R.R.2d 1313 (1982) [sic4 ] and Mid-Florida Television Corp., 60 F.C.C.2d 607 Rev.Bd. (1978) [sic5 ], which were effective prior to September 12, 1986, other than to close MM Docket No. 86-484 with a reinstatement of prior policy and a lifting of suspension of any sales, licenses, applications, or proceedings, which were suspended pending the conclusion of the inquiry....
In compliance with this provision, the FCC ended reconsideration of its comparative preference and distress sale policies, without issuing any conclusions, and announced it would reinstate such policies as they existed prior to September 12, 1986. See, e.g., Faith Center, Inc., 3 F.C.C.Rcd. 868 (1988).
Shurberg promptly moved the court for expedited resolution on the merits. Shur-berg noted that the case was fully briefed and argued more than two years ago, and that the termination of the Steele inquiry precluded any further evolution of the case. We granted the motion in part, agreeing to render our decision on the merits in the normal course of business. The FCC’s request for a remand to allow it to reexamine the distress sale policy, as well as its brief in Steele, suggested that it may now essentially agree with Shurberg’s constitutional arguments.
On the other hand, I also recognize that the FCC’s brief in Winter Park Communications v. FCC, Nos. 85-1755 and 85-1756, (D.C.Cir. argued Nov. 21, 1988) is supportive of the Commission’s minority preference policy as used in its comparative licensing procedures. The FCC asserted that approach is constitutional because it is based on the compelling government interest in the enhancement of diversity of programming — a contention which appears inconsistent with its brief in Steele. Still, in Winter Park, the FCC argued that its policy was narrowly tailored because “race is one of several factors to be considered rather than a decisive factor in and of itself.” Therefore, since race is only one
The continuing resolution apparently has prevented the formal expression of any further views by the FCC in this case, and the distress sale policy, reinstated by the FCC, is still operative and has an effect on Shur-berg’s interests. We therefore must consider his challenge, looking to the various briefs, which paradoxically include both the FCC’s defense and repudiation of its policy.
II.
Turning first to Shurberg’s nonconstitu-tional challenge to the Commission’s action, the major issue presented is the propriety of the Commission’s decision that Shurberg was not entitled to a comparative hearing. Giving appropriate deference to the FCC’s construction and application of its rules, see San Luis Obispo Mothers for Peace v. NRC, 789 F.2d 26, 30 (D.C.Cir.) (en banc), cert. denied, 479 U.S. 923, 107 S.Ct. 330, 93 L.Ed.2d 302 (1986), I discern no basis for overturning the FCC’s determination on this ground.
The Communications Act of 1934, as amended, provides that licenses in hearing status shall remain in effect pending final disposition of the hearing. See 47 U.S.C. § 307(c). The FCC’s regulations, moreover, provide that the Commission will not accept competitive applications after a certain time, in order to allow the Commission to designate renewal applications for hearing and to conduct such hearings in an orderly fashion. See 47 C.F.R. § 73.3516(e) (1987); City of Angels Broadcasting v. FCC, 745 F.2d 656, 662-64 (D.C.Cir.1984). In my view, the Commission properly applied the statute and its regulations when it refused to accept Shurberg’s competitive application while a hearing on Faith Center’s qualifications was pending. Shurberg argues that the posture of Faith Center’s renewal application was really more akin to deferred status than to designated-for-hearing status and under the rule of New South Media, 685 F.2d 708, the substance and not the form of a license’s status is controlling. As I have mentioned, designated-for-hearing applications are protected from competitive filings, but deferred applications are not. Deferred applicants are required to submit supplemental renewal applications at every interval during the time of their deferred status when a regular renewal application would be due. And those supplemental filings operate to open a window for competitive applications.
In New South Media, the FCC had granted several renewal applications conditioned upon the outcome of a comparative renewal proceeding involving another of the licensee’s licenses. Later the FCC denied renewal of that other license and decided to hold noncomparative hearings to determine how to treat the conditionally renewed licenses. Instead of waiting for the remaining licenses to expire and evaluating each at that time against competing applications, the Commission decided to reopen the earlier conditional renewals by designating those applications for hearing. Id. at 710. As the hearings were to begin after completion of all court appeals involving the unrenewed license, the FCC could fix no specific date for the hearings. This court overturned the FCC’s decision to hold the applications in designated-for-hearing status, shielded from competition for an interval longer than the license period itself. We found the situation analogous to that in Carlisle Broadcasting Associates, 59 F.C.C.2d 885 (1976), in which the FCC ruled that when a renewal application had remained in deferred status for three years (which was the license term), the Commission would entertain competing applications. See New South Media, 685 F.2d at 716. Between the time the FCC had designated the licenses for hearing and the com
Shurberg argues that under New South Media the mere designation of a hearing is not sufficient to preclude competing applications, that there must actually be an ongoing renewal proceeding which would otherwise be hampered. Faith Center’s attempts to consummate a distress sale, it is asserted, cannot themselves be regarded as “administrative activity” sufficient to justify the Commission’s treatment of the Faith Center renewal proceeding as ongoing.
I disagree with Shurberg’s view of New South Media’s bearing on this case. New South Media treated the absence of ongoing administrative proceedings as a factor militating against keeping the renewal applications in protected status, but did not rule out the possibility that other interests might warrant continued protection against competitive applications. That competitive applications might disrupt ongoing proceedings is only one facet of a larger concern for administration of the FCC’s mandate. For the distress sale policy to work, the FCC must have the discretion to hold a renewal application in designated-for-hearing status long enough to permit the licensee to explore the possibility of such a sale. In this case, the FCC exercised its discretion to hold the application in designated-for-hearing status not once, but three times. All in all, the application was in deferred status for over three years and then in designated-for-hearing status for four years. Admittedly, that is a long time for competitors to be precluded from filing their applications, but I do not see here the total absence of administrative activity that was apparent in New South Media. The Commission’s efforts to allow Faith Center to avail itself of an FCC policy were not so unreasonable as to require reversal.
As Shurberg acknowledges, New South Media recognized that not all limitations on the Ashbacker policy of favoring competition are impermissible, especially insofar as they advance the FCC’s orderly administration of its work. See 685 F.2d at 716. If the distress sale policy were constitutional, it would present sufficiently weighty grounds for a limited exception to the Ash-backer policy. Because an agency’s balancing of competing policy considerations is entitled to considerable deference from a court, Chevron U.S.A. Inc. v. Natural Resources Defense Council, 467 U.S. 837, 843-44, 104 S.Ct. 2778, 2782, 81 L.Ed.2d 694 (1984), I would be obliged to respect the Commission’s decision to implement the distress sale policy despite attendant delays. Accordingly, I do not quarrel with the Commission on this basis.
III.
Shurberg challenges the distress sale policy as ultra vires on both statutory and constitutional grounds. We are, of course, normally obliged to consider the statutory question first — whether the policy exceeds congressional authorization — and I am mindful of the maxim that we construe statutes narrowly to avoid constitutional infirmities. Crowell v. Benson, 285 U.S. 22, 62, 52 S.Ct. 285, 297, 76 L.Ed. 598 (1932). Still, the Commission operates under a broad statutory mandate to consider the “public interest, convenience and necessity.” 47 U.S.C. § 309(a) (1982). Congress
A.
The constitutional issue is whether or not the distress sale policy, by creating a preference for minority purchasers, violates the equal protection component of the Fifth Amendment. See Bolling v. Sharpe, 347 U.S. 497, 74 S.Ct. 693, 98 L.Ed. 884 (1954). The Supreme Court has struggled with the constitutionality of government-sponsored minority preferences four times in the last ten years,
Bakke struck down a university admissions policy that set aside a fixed percentage of each class,for minority candidates. In the majority, only Justice Powell’s opinion reached the constitutional issue, and in discussing the possible justifications for the admissions program, he firmly rejected the notion that a racial classification could be based on a mere desire to assure that the student body contained specified percentages of particular racial and ethnic groups. 438 U.S. at 307, 98 S.Ct. at 2757. He also rejected the use of a preference as a remedy for past discrimination, because the university had not made any findings of discrimination, and indeed was not competent to make such findings. Id. at 307-09, 98 S.Ct. at 2757-58. Justice Powell’s opinion, however, did recognize that an academic institution has a compelling interest in promoting a diverse educational environment. Id. at 311-14, 98 S.Ct. at 2759-60. Bringing together students from diverse ethnic and cultural backgrounds allows them “to learn from their differences and to stimulate one another to reexamine even their most deeply held assumptions about themselves and their world.” Id. at 313 n. 48, 98 S.Ct. at 2760 n. 48 (citation omitted). Racial diversity is a legitimate aspect of a diverse student body, but it is only one part of the “genuine diversity” that is a compelling state interest. Id. at 315, 98 S.Ct. at 2761. Thus, the university could have used race as one factor in a multi-factor admissions decision. But simply employing a racial set-aside was inconsistent with the attainment of “genuine diversity,” an interest that would necessarily require consideration of factors other than race. See id. at 315-18, 98 S.Ct. at 2761-62.
Fullilove is the only case in which the Court has sustained the constitutionality of a governmentally-imposed minority preference not occasioned by a court’s remedial
In Wygant, the Court held unconstitutional a school layoff policy that accorded minority teachers a preference over nonmi-norities with seniority. As Justice O’Con-nor concurred in the Court’s judgment on narrow grounds and no other opinion was joined by five justices, one may take Justice O’Connor’s separate concurrence, and those parts of Justice Powell’s opinion in which she also concurred, to represent the holding of the Court. See Marks v. United States, 430 U.S. 188, 193, 97 S.Ct. 990, 993. The Court found that the school board had failed to establish the necessary factual predicate — i.e., evidence of past discrimination — for remedial action. See 476 U.S. at 277-78, 106 S.Ct. at 1848-49. The Court, however, relaxed its previous requirement that the governmental body make “findings” of discrimination. Recognizing that such findings might subject a government to liability, the Court authorized preferences to be predicated on substantial evidence of discrimination. Wygant, 476 U.S. at 289-92, 106 S.Ct. at 1854-56 (O’Connor, J., concurring). Flatly rejected, though, as a legitimate justification for the preferences was the school’s asserted need to provide minority role models; such a theory, the Court maintained, has “no logical stopping point.” Id. at 275-76, 106 S.Ct. at 1848. Essentially, the Court (Justice O’Connor) held that the layoff provision was not narrowly tailored to achieve its remedial purpose, because the hiring goal that the provision was designed to protect was calculated as a ratio of black teachers to black students, rather than as a ratio of black teachers to qualified minority teach
Croson, the Court’s most recent pronouncement, held unconstitutional Richmond’s Minority Business Utilization Plan, which required prime contractors awarded city construction contracts to subcontract at least thirty percent of the dollar amount of each contract to one or more “Minority Business Enterprises.” The Court ruled that a racial preference, at least when implemented by a state or local government, is subject to “strict scrutiny” review under the Equal Protection Clause. Croson, at -, 109 S.Ct. at 721; id. at -, 109 S.Ct. at 734-35 (Scalia, J., concurring). Given this standard of review, the Richmond plan was not supported by a sufficient factual predicate for remedial action. The City Council’s evidence was deficient, because “a generalized assertion that there has been past discrimination in an entire industry provides no guidance for a legislative body to determine the precise scope of the injury it seeks to remedy.” Id. at -, 109 S.Ct. at 723-24. In particular, the Court ruled that mere assertions of a “benign” purpose for the racial classification were “entitled to little or no weight,” id., and that a comparison between the number of prime contracts awarded to minority firms and the minority population of the city (as opposed to the number of qualified minority firms) is inappropriate. Id. at -, 109 S.Ct. at 725-26. The Richmond plan also failed the test of narrow tailoring because there had been no “consideration of the use of race-neutral means to increase minority business participation in city contracting,” id. at -, 109 S.Ct. at 727, nor did the plan provide for an “inquiry into whether or not the particular MBE seeking a racial preference ha[d] suffered from the effects of past discrimination_” Id. at -, 109 S.Ct. at 729-30.
Some general propositions may be gleaned from these four cases. Govern-mentally-imposed minority preferences are constitutionally permissible under certain limited circumstances, but they may not be based on the desirability per se of achieving racial balance or proportional representation of minorities in selected institutions. The Court has recognized that the objective of remedying past discrimination may justify the use of minority preferences, see Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 475, 100 S.Ct. at 2773, and at least one Justice has viewed promoting diversity in an educational context as a second compelling state interest. See Bakke, 438 U.S. at 311-15, 98 S.Ct. at 2759-61 (opinion of Powell, J.).
The nature of the evidence required to establish the existence of prior discrimination varies with the authority of the governmental body imposing the remedial preference. See Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 515 n. 14, 100 S.Ct. at 2793 n. 14 (Powell, J., concurring). Congress is clearly the institution with the most latitude to make findings of discrimination and authorize remedies on the basis of the evidence before it. See Croson, at -, 109 S.Ct. at 719-20; Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 472, 483, 100 S.Ct. at 2771, 2777; id. at 499-502, 100 S.Ct. at 2785-87 (Powell, J., concurring).
Assuming the factual predicate for remedial action by any governmental body has been established, a reviewing court must still ensure that the use of race is narrowly tailored to the remedial purpose. Croson, at -, 109 S.Ct. at 728; Wygant, 476 U.S. at 274, 106 S.Ct. 1847. Most important, a racial preference plan must allow for case-by-case consideration of applicants to ensure that each minority has in fact suffered from the effects of past discrimination. See Croson, at -, -, 109 S.Ct. at 719, 727-30; Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 486-87, 100 S.Ct. at 2779. The preference
Aside from remedying past discrimination, the only other state interest heretofore identified in a Supreme Court opinion and upheld as sufficiently compelling to support race-conscious policies is the promotion of diversity in a school’s student body. Bakke, 438 U.S. at 311-12, 98 S.Ct. at 2759 (opinion of Powell, J.). In Bakke, Justice Powell emphasized the special role and characteristics of institutions of higher learning and the First Amendment protections afforded them. Id. at 312-13, 98 S.Ct. at 2759-60 Pursuit of diversity, in his view, is a compelling basis for affirmative discrimination only in circumstances and settings, such as those found in academia, where “a countervailing constitutional interest, that of the First Amendment,” in the selection of students “is of paramount importance in the fulfillment of [the institution’s] mission.” Id. at 313, 98 S.Ct. at 2760. Seeking racial or ethnic diversity for its own sake in a governmental or government-regulated institution has been soundly rejected. It is synonymous with the illegitimate objective of racial balance or proportional representation and is thus equivalent to “discrimination for its own sake.” Id. at 307, 98 S.Ct. at 2757. Preferring minorities in order to create role-models has been similarly rejected because it too leads inexorably to explicit racial balancing. See Wygant, 476 U.S. at 274-76, 106 S.Ct. at 1847-48 Britton v. South Bend Community School Corp., 819 F.2d 766, 767-68 (7th Cir.) (en banc), cert. denied, — U.S. —, 108 S.Ct. 288, 98 L.Ed. 2d 248 (1987). The goal of racial diversity might be compelling then only when that greater diversity itself serves one of society’s fundamental goals. See Bakke, 438 U.S. at 311-15, 98 S.Ct. at 2759-61.
Even if the government is seeking racial diversity for a legitimate educational purpose, a court must still ask if the form and manner of the racial classification used is appropriate to achieve that purpose — again, whether the race-conscious measure is narrowly tailored. Id. at 315, 98 S.Ct. at 2761. The constitutional test for “narrow tailoring” appears to be slightly different when the government’s justification for a racial preference is the promotion of diversity (so far recognized only in an academic setting) rather than the remedy of past discrimination. The Court has rejected the use of minority set-asides as a means of promoting diversity. See id. at 315-18, 98 S.Ct. at 2761-62. Because ethnic (or racial) origin is just one of many factors that combine to create “genuine diversity” in an educational environment, the state’s interest is better promoted when ancestry is one element of a multi-factor evaluation that takes into consideration a variety of characteristics and attributes. Id. According to the Court (Justice Powell), the crucial requirement for a program that uses a racial preference to enhance legitimate diversity is that each applicant must receive individualized consideration. Bakke, 438 U.S. at 318 & n. 52, 98 S.Ct. at 2762 n. 52.
The FCC appears to justify its policy both as a means to foster diverse programming and as a remedy for past discrimination. Although the Commission’s brief emphasizes that the distress sale policy is “based principally” on its authority to promote diversity of programming, and the dissent suggests that the policy rests “exclusively on the diversity rationale,” dissent at 953, I feel obliged to address the
B.
The Court in Croson reaffirmed the plurality’s view in Wygant that, when considering actions by state and local governments, “[sjocietal discrimination, without more, is too amorphous a basis for imposing a racially classified remedy.” Croson, at -, 109 S.Ct. at 723-24 (quoting Wygant, 476 U.S. at 276, 106 S.Ct. at 1848). In dicta, however, three members of the majority read Fullilove to mean that, in certain circumstances, Congress, in the exercise of its powers under section five of the Fourteenth Amendment, could constitutionally “identify and redress the effects of society-wide discrimination.” Croson, at -, 109 S.Ct. at 720. If we are to conclude that the FCC has provided a sufficient factual predicate for the distress sale policy, we must rest on that dicta, because the indications of past discrimination used by the FCC to justify its program are only of the most general nature. Four years after the FCC implemented its distress sale policy, Congress commented that “the effects of past inequities stemming from racial and ethnic discrimination have resulted in a severe underrepresentation of minorities in the mass media communication, as it has adversely affected their participation in other sectors of the economy as well.” H.R.Conf.Rep. No. 765, 97th Cong., 2d Sess. 43 (1982) (emphasis added). The report cited statistics showing that minority-owned broadcasting stations accounted for less than two percent of commercial broadcasting stations. See id. The FCC had made similar findings of minority “under-representation”
Neither Congress nor the FCC ever found any evidence to link minority “under-representation” to discrimination by the FCC or to particular discriminatory practices in the broadcasting industry.
I do not read the Court’s dicta in Croson to mean that Congress may act without some quantum of particularized evidence of the effects of societal discrimination in the relevant industry, and in that regard the general findings of minority underrep-resentation in the broadcasting field differ, in my view, from the congressional findings the Court encountered in Fullilove. In that case, Congress had “abundant evidence from which it could conclude that minority businesses have been denied effective participation in public contracting opportunities by procurement practices that perpetuated the effects of prior discrimination.” Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 477-78, 100 S.Ct. at 2774. In the case of broadcasting, the evidence before Congress of the treatment of minorities in the broadcast industry was considerably less particularized. Underrepresentation alone cannot be sufficient proof of the effects of past societal discrimination. There is, of course, the possibility that minorities may be “disproportionately attracted to industries other than [broadcasting].” Croson, at -, 109 S.Ct. at 725-26; see also Johnson v. Transportation Agency, 480 U.S. 616, 668, 107 S.Ct. 1442, 1471, 94 L.Ed.2d 615 (1987) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (phenomena of discrimination and underrepresentation due to social attitudes are “certainly distinct”). If we were to hold that Congress may authorize a racial set-aside based on the meager evidence presented here, I do not see what would prevent Congress from mandating proportional racial representation in all publicly-controlled employment opportunities.
Nevertheless, assuming arguendo that the broadcasting field has been plagued by the type of “societal discrimination” to which the Court referred in Croson and that Congress has the power to authorize its redress, the FCC’s program does not conform to the stricture of the Constitution because it is not narrowly tailored to remedy past discrimination. That a remedial preference must be narrowly tailored implies, as I understand the concept, three distinct limitations. The degree of preference must be tied to the effects of past disadvantages or discrimination, see Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 486-88, 100 S.Ct. at 2779-80; Croson, at -, 109 S.Ct. at 719, 727-30; there must be prior consideration of the use of race-neutral means to increase minority participation, see Croson, at -, 109 S.Ct. at 727; Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 463-67, 100 S.Ct. at 2767-69; id. at 511, 100 S.Ct. at 2792 (Powell, J., concurring); and the burden the preference imposes on innocent third parties must not be unfair. See Wygant, 476 U.S. at 282-84, 106 S.Ct. at 1851-52; Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 484, 100 S.Ct. at 2777. The distress sale policy is deficient in each respect.
The price of the distress sale is set by bargaining between a minority purchaser who is insulated from nonminority competition and a seller who is presumably anxious to salvage some value for his license and assets. The discount to the minority purchaser — in one sense, the degree of the preference — is likely to be substantial. Indeed, in order to preserve some deterrent against violating basic qualification requirements, the Commission prescribes that a distress sale price may not exceed seventy-five percent of the station’s fair market value, see Lee Broadcasting Corp., 76 F.C.C.2d 462, 463 (1980), thus guaranteeing the minority purchaser a discount of at least twenty-five percent. In this case, Astroline purchased WHCT at a forty-seven percent of the average appraised value.
The FCC rules in no way require the preference to be tied to the extent of disadvantage suffered by the minority enterprise. There is no opportunity here to ensure that participating minority enterprises have actually been disadvantaged by past discrimination or its effects. See Croson, at -, 109 S.Ct. at 730; Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 487-89, 100 S.Ct. at 2779-80. The Commission apparently found Astroline to be eligible to participate in the distress sale simply because of Ramirez’s Hispanic surname.
Unlike the plan in Fullilove, it does not appear that Congress or the FCC chose adoption of a racial preference only after consideration and rejection of race-neutral means to increase minority ownership of broadcast stations. See Croson, at -, 109 S.Ct. at 719; Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 463-67, 100 S.Ct. at 2767-69 (Congress carefully examined and rejected race-neutral alternatives before enacting the MBE set-aside); id. at 511, 100 S.Ct. at 2792 (Powell, J., concurring). After identifying lack of information and lack of financing as the principal entry barriers working against people outside the “old-boy network,” see dissent at 937 the FCC did not consider race-neutral measures to increase dissemination of information about stations up for sale or to provide financing for prospective purchasers. Instead, the FCC opted immediately for racial preferences, both in the granting of tax-deferred certificates and in the authorization of distress sales. 1978 Policy Statement, 68 F.C.C.2d at 982-84. The agency’s conduct, therefore, is contrary to the direction of the Court in Croson and Fullilove that racial classifications may be employed only as a last resort.
I also believe that the distress sale policy requires innocent third parties to shoulder an excessive burden. The important question in the case of a remedial racial preference appears to be how directly and harshly a disadvantage falls on a nonminority. See Wygant, 476 U.S. at 282-83, 106 S.Ct. at 1851 (opinion of Powell, J.); Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 484, 100 S.Ct. at 2777. In Fullilove, for instance, the Court found the “actual ‘burden’ shouldered by nonminority firms is relatively light.” Id.; see also id. at 521, 100 S.Ct. at 2797 (Marshall, J., concurring). This was so because the public construction funds at issue constituted only two and one-half percent of all funds spent on contracting each year in the United States. The ten percent set-aside reserved for minorities amounted to only one-fourth of one percent of all construction contracting opportunities. Id. at 484 n. 72, 100 S.Ct. at 2777 n. 72. Similarly, in Wygant, the plurality opinion struck down a race-conscious layoff provision, in large part because “layoffs impose the entire burden of achieving racial equality on particular individuals.” 476 U.S. at 283, 106 S.Ct. at 1851. The employees in Wygant had developed a web of associations that would have made involuntary separation particularly painful even if other jobs were readily available. The uniqueness of the existing job made its potential deprivation an unconstitutional burden.
The distress sale policy imposes an unconstitutional burden on Shurberg because it deprives him of a unique opportunity to own a broadcasting station, solely because of his race. Unlike the construction-industry plaintiffs in Fullilove, whose prospective opportunities in the private sector greatly mitigated the theoretical hardship on any hypothetical individual contractor,
The dissent argues that the policy is narrowly tailored because only thirty-three stations were transferred to minorities through this technique since 1978. Dissent at 36. That is, as the dissent observes, a small percentage of the total broadcast licenses held in the United States, although I do not know what percentage of recent license transfers this number represents. But, in any event, this is not a facial challenge as in Fullilove, and these statistics are of little consequence to Shurberg; the burden on him is not lessened because only thirty-three other stations have been transferred by this technique. There is no reason to conclude that he shares a community of interest with other nonminority station owners spread throughout the country that might cushion his adverse treatment. It is a Hartford station Shurberg wants and, after all is said and done, he has been absolutely denied an opportunity to compete for one merely because of his race. A chance to compete for a license elsewhere in the country is not an equivalent opportunity for Shurberg. As an applicant for a license outside of Hartford, he would be at a material disadvantage because of the competitive enhancement the FCC accords applicants with ties to the local community. See West Michigan Broadcasting Co. v. FCC, 735 F.2d 601, 606 (D.C.Cir.1984), cert. denied, 470 U.S. 1027, 105 S.Ct. at 1392, 84 L.Ed.2d 782 (1985).
Shurberg’s situation is also analogous to the nonminority employees in Wygant Like the layoff provision in Wygant, the operation of the distress sale policy places a direct burden on a small group of individuals: those seeking to enter the broadcast industry in a particular market. The dissent, drawing on Wygant, contends that Shurberg's posture is to be compared to a
C.
The FCC also justifies the distress sale policy as a means of promoting programming diversity.
At the outset, I recognize that racial or ethnic diversity has been formally identified as a compelling government interest by only one Justice of the Supreme Court in Bakke.
In Bakke, Justice Powell saw diversity in institutions of higher education as a compelling state interest that justified racial preferences. It is vital to the educational mission, he concluded, that all students have “ ‘wide exposure’ to the ideas and mores of students as diverse as this Nation of many peoples.” Bakke, 438 U.S. at 313, 98 S.Ct. at 2760. Crucial to his analysis was the fact that diversity benefited not just the preferred group, but all students and eventually the entire nation. Essentially, Justice Powell felt that the state has a compelling interest in requiring students to be exposed to a wide variety of people during their higher education.
We considered the suggested analogy between diversity of student bodies in institutions of higher education and diversity of broadcast programming in West Michigan Broadcasting Co. v. FCC, 735 F.2d 601, 614-15 (D.C.Cir.1984). At that time, we concluded that “the FCC’s goal of bringing minority perspectives to the nation’s listening audiences would reflect a substantial government interest ... that could legitimize the use of race as a factor in evaluating permit applications.” Id. at 614. For the time being, therefore, our precedent compels the conclusion that there is a compelling government interest in increasing diversity of programming.
Whatever the legal validity of the FCC policy at issue in West Michigan, that precedent cannot support the Commission’s desire to promote diversity through the distress sale policy, because the FCC itself has determined that there no longer is an inadequate diversity of viewpoints in television programming. The FCC recently determined that the fairness doctrine, aimed at promoting balanced broadcast presentations on matters of public interest, was
But, assuming that West Michigan survives both Croson and the renunciation of the fairness doctrine, and is binding precedent on this point — that the FCC has a compelling interest in seeking racial or ethnic programming diversity when distributing broadcasting licenses — I am still faced with the issue whether a preference for minority ownership (or management) is an appropriate (narrowly tailored) means with which to achieve such programming diversity. The minority distress sale policy does not award a preference for diverse programming. Instead, the policy seeks to promote diversity of programming indirectly by limiting minority distress sale opportunities to broadcasting entities “with a significant minority ownership interest.” 1978 Policy Statement, 68 F.C.C.2d at 983. As a means to promote diverse programming, the distress sale policy rests on the questionable premise that minority ownership will by itself lead to minority programming (or programming that might be thought to have a minority perspective).
My dissenting colleague insists that our decision in West Michigan controls this issue as well, but I find that contention unpersuasive. The Supreme Court’s subsequent decisions in Wygant and Croson undermine West Michigan’s determination of a nexus between ownership and programming, and we are thus not bound by West Michigan on that issue. See Dellums v. NRC, 863 F.2d 968, 978 n. 11 (D.C.Cir.1988).
The dissent maintains that it is “entirely foreseeable” that minority broadcasters “will have distinct perspectives to convey.” Dissent at 944. That statement more-or-less reflects the analysis of West Michigan, which held that the FCC may rely on a “[reasonable expectation” that minority owners are likely to increase diversity of content. West Michigan, 735 F.2d at 610 (reaffirming TV 9, Inc. v. FCC, 495 F.2d 929, 937-38 (D.C.Cir.1973), cert. denied, 419 U.S. 986, 95 S.Ct. 245, 42 L.Ed.2d 194 (1974)).
The Court in Croson reiterated the im-permissibility of stereotyping. Justice Stevens remarked that “the Richmond City Council has merely engaged in the type of stereotypical analysis that is a hallmark of violations of the Equal Protection Clause.” Croson, at -, 109 S.Ct. at 733-34 (Stevens, J., concurring). In my view, that is exactly what this eourt in West Michigan (and subsequently the FCC) has done by relying on a “reasonable expectation,” without any supportive findings, that every minority owner will produce minority programming. As the Supreme Court aptly put it, “[ajbsent such findings, there is a danger that a racial classification is merely the product of unthinking stereotypes or a form of racial politics.” Id. at -, 109 S.Ct. at 732. And certainly, a desire to avoid the bureaucratic effort required to consider whether individual license applicants will increase diversity of programming cannot justify a racial generalization. Id.
If we simply assume that individual minority members have a comparative advantage in devising programs that appeal to their own racial or ethnic group, we would
In any event, it is not at all apparent why a station owner, be she minority or nonmi-nority, would make programming decisions according to her personal tastes rather than in response to the demands of the marketplace. In its Steele brief, for example, the FCC explained that it has determined in a series of rulemaking proceedings that market forces are the primary creators of diverse programming.
It is also argued that Congress made findings that support the nexus between program diversity and minority ownership when it approved a lottery system for the selection of broadcast licenses. See H.R. Rep. No. 765, 97th Cong., 2d Sess. (1982). Although the holding of Fullilove is that Congress may act to remedy past discrimination based upon less particularized historical evidence than would be required of another governmental body or a court of law, it is not clear whether the same authority exists outside the remedial context. Whatever its authority, the House conference report regarding the lottery system is not instructive as to the existence of a nexus between program diversity and minority ownership. Significantly, the report does not purport to make historical findings of fact, as did Congress in enacting the set-aside plan at issue in Fullilove. Rather, the statements concerning the existence of a nexus between ownership and programming are in the nature of predictions as to future behavior. Nowhere in the House report is there evidence presented of a nexus between program diversity and minority ownership, nor is there reference to evidence upon which the committee drew. There are simply assertions that the former will follow from the latter. See, e.g., id. at 40 (“The nexus between diversity of media ownership and diversity of programming services has been repeatedly recognized by both the Commission and the courts.”);
The closest thing to an actual historical finding is that “the Conferees find that the effects of past inequities stemming from racial and ethnic discrimination have resulted in a severe underrepresentation of minorities in the media of mass communications, as it has adversely affected their participation in other sectors of the economy as well.” H.R.Rep. No. 765, 97th Cong., 2d Sess. 43 (1982). This finding of “underrepresentation” does nothing to establish the nexus between minority owner
I respectfully submit that my position— concerning the effect to be given the House conference report — is hardly “judicial presumptiveness,” dissent at 940, or a “belittlement of Congress,” dissent at 946 n. 29, as the dissent accuses. Rather, to defer to such ipse dixit would be judicial abdication. If my dissenting colleague is correct, and mere congressional assertion without the support of any material developed in congressional hearings is adequate to justify a system of distribution of broadcast licenses based on race, then the Supreme Court’s language in Fullilove focusing on the evidence of discrimination in government contracting that was brought before Congress was just empty rhetoric.
In my view, therefore, the FCC’s attempt to justify the distress sale policy through analogy to the diversity goal recognized as compelling by Justice Powell in Bakke is inadequate. However, even assuming the dissent’s view that the FCC has cleared all the hurdles I have described, the distress sale policy clearly fails the Bakke test for narrow tailoring.
In Bakke, Justice Powell condemned the use of a racial preference designed to promote diversity when race was the only factor considered in certain admissions decisions:
The diversity that furthers a compelling state interest encompasses a far broader array of qualifications and characteristics of which racial or ethnic origin is but a single though important element. Petitioner’s special admissions program, focused solely on ethnic diversity, would hinder rather than further attainment of genuine diversity.
Bakke, 438 U.S. at 315, 98 S.Ct. at 2761 (footnote omitted).
The distress sale policy shares the same flaw as the special admissions quota struck down in Bakke. Instead of considering the broad range of factors that would lead a prospective station owner to contribute to diverse programming, the policy singles out one aspect of diversity and elevates it to determinative status. Shurberg was “foreclosed from all consideration for [the
D.
What is truly extraordinary about this case is that after the FCC (the creator of the distress sale policy) admitted that it had not adequately established a nexus between minority status and broadcast diversity to withstand constitutional scrutiny and this court, in light of that admission, ordered a remand to enable the FCC to reconsider the issue, Congress intervened with a continuing resolution to prevent the FCC from expending funds to pursue that inquiry in accordance with our remand order. The conference report accompanying the resolution said “[t]he Committee also instructs the Commission to resolve within 60 days all proceedings that have been remanded by the court of appeals, including ... Shurberg Broadcasting of Hartford, Inc. v. Federal Communications Commission, No. 84-1600 (D.C.Cir. ordered remanded June 25, 1987).” S. Rep. No. 182, 100th Cong., 1st Sess. 77 (1987). Not surprisingly, the FCC complied with congressional direction rather than our remand order, closed the docket in which the Shurberg case was considered, and, in accordance with the continuing resolution, reinstated its prior distress sale policy.
******
In sum, the FCC has a policy in search of a justification. While the Commission claims to be principally pursuing diversity of programming, it uses racial stereotypes as a proxy for such diversity, and alternatively relies for support on congressional authority to remedy the effects of past racial discrimination. The dissent purports to rely exclusively on the diversity rationale, but seeks to strengthen the FCC’s position with references to remedial goals and authority. Whichever purposes actually motivated the FCC, the policy cannot withstand equal protection scrutiny.
It is doubtful that the FCC has a compelling interest in fostering programming diversity, and even if it does, the agency has failed to show that there exists a nexus between minority ownership and diversity of program content. Nonminorities interested in particular licenses are completely excluded by the operation of the policy, and it therefore fails the requirement of narrow tailoring enunciated in Bakke.
The remedial rationale fares no better. The historical basis for the plan is only general findings of underrepresentation, which might not even be a result of “societal discrimination” as used by the Court in Croson. If “remedial,” as used in Croson, carries the soft imprecise meaning that Chief Judge Wald suggests, see dissent at 953 n. 48, there really is no constitutional barrier to Congress legislating racial and ethnic proportional representation for beneficiaries of government programs or federal employees. In any event, the distress sale policy is not narrowly tailored to remedy past discrimination, because its effect is unrelated to the need for such a remedy, and it provides no procedures for ensuring that the policy’s beneficiaries have actually suffered from the effects of past discrimination. There is no indication, moreover, that the FCC sought to employ race-neutral programs to aid minorities before resorting to a racial set-aside. Finally, the distress sale policy imposes a heavy burden on innocent minorities by completely depriving them of opportunities to compete for unique television outlets.
Shurberg challenged the constitutionality of the distress sale policy only as a last resort in this proceeding and only after years of seeking an opportunity to compete openly and fairly for a television license in Hartford. We too have sought, procedurally and analytically, to avoid deciding this important constitutional question. I think, however, that I have no alternative now but to conclude that the FCC’s distress sale policy as applied to Shurberg is unconstitutional.
. The FCC has stated that a qualified minority enterprise is one that meets the Commission’s basic qualifications and in which the minority ownership interest exceeds 50% or is controlling. See Commission Policy Regarding the Advancement of Minority Ownership in Broadcasting, 92 F.C.C.2d 849, 853 (1982) (“1982 Policy Statement"). A special policy applies to limited partnerships: If there is a general partner who is a minority with a 20% interest in the partnership, the enterprise qualifies as one with "significant minority involvement.” Id. at 855.
. The distress sale policy is not without attraction to the station owner whose license has been designated for hearing. By selling his station, even at a 25% discount, the owner avoids the "costs of a renewal hearing and the risk of a revoked license." Comment, FCC Minority Distress Sale Policy: Public Interest v. The Public’s Interest, 1981 Wisc.L.Rev. 365, 366 (1981).
. This court has jurisdiction pursuant to section 402(b) of the Communications Act, 47 U.S.C. § 402(b) (1982).
. 52 Rad.Reg.2d (P & F) 1301 (1982).
. 69 F.C.C.2d 607 (Rev.Bd.1978).
. I express no opinion as to the validity of the minority preference policy in the comparative license practice raised in Winter Park.
. The dissent, although agreeing with the FCC that this issue presents a “close question,” seems to concur on this point, dissent at 935 n. 3; otherwise the dissent presumably would not reach the constitutional question.
. I also reject Shurberg’s argument that the FCC’s proceedings were fatally tainted by ex parte communications and other irregularities. None of the alleged communications warrants a remand. FCC regulations prohibit only ex parte communications "directed to the merits or outcome of a proceeding.” 47 C.F.R. § 1.1202(a) (1987). Only one of the alleged communications, a memorandum to the Commissioners from a non-decisionmaking employee, went to the merits of the Faith Center proceeding. The Commission has since included that memorandum in the record of this proceeding. It is obvious from reading the memorandum that the Commission's failure to make it public before it acted did not harm Shurberg in any meaningful respect. See PATCO v. Federal Labor Relations Authority, 685 F.2d 547, 564-65 (D.C.Cir.1982).
. A fifth case. Local 28 of the Sheet Metal Workers' Int'l Ass'n v. EEOC, 478 U.S. 421, 106 S.Ct. 3019, 92 L.Ed.2d 344 (1986), is distinct both because it involved a court-ordered, remedy to discrimination and because it dealt primarily with Title VII.
. Court-ordered racial classifications have been sustained when used to remedy proven discrimination. See, e.g., Local 28 of the Sheet Metal Workers' Int'l Ass’n v. EEOC, 478 U.S. 421, 106 S.Ct. 3019, 92 L.Ed.2d 344 (1986); Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Bd. of Educ., 402 U.S. 1, 91 S.Ct. 1267, 28 L.Ed.2d 554 (1971).
. The plaintiffs in Fullilove did not seek damages or other specific relief for injuries caused by the application of the program, but only declaratory and injunctive relief striking down the program in toto. Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 480-81 & n. 71, 100 S.Ct. at 2775-76 & n. 71. The Court was not asked to consider the fairness of the burden borne by particular individuals; it observed that "questions of specific application must await future cases.” Id. at 486, 100 S.Ct. at 2779.
. For a discussion of Congress’ special role under the enforcement provision of the Fourteenth Amendment, see Nathanson, Congressional Power To Contradict the Supreme Court’s Constitutional Decisions: Accommodation of Rights in Conflict, 27 Wm. & Mary L.Rev. 331, 356-57 (1986).
. The dissent appears to agree, albeit for different reasons, that the distress sale policy cannot be sustained as a remedial program. See dissent at 935, 953. That is not entirely clear, however, since at other times the dissent characterizes the distress sale policy as “an effort to remedy the effects of past discrimination,” id. at 942, and relies on "the broad remedial powers of Congress.” Id. at 942.
. By "underrepresentation,” Congress and the FCC seem to have meant that the percentage of stations owned by minorities was less than the percentage of minorities in the population as a whole.
.The Minority Ownership Task Force report, to which the FCC’s 1978 Policy Statement refers, suggests that minority entry into the broadcasting industry is primarily hindered by difficulties in obtaining financing. But, minorities' lack of money is not linked to specific discriminatory practices.
. Recently, the Court suggested that the analysis in Croson is relevant to federally-mandated racial preference policies when it vacated for reconsideration in light of Croson the Eleventh Circuit’s decision in H.K. Porter Co. v. Metropolitan Dade County, 825 F.2d 324 (11th Cir.1987). See — U.S. —, 109 S.Ct. 1333, 103 L.Ed.2d 804 (1989). In H.K. Porter, the court upheld Dade County’s policy of requiring five percent participation by minority business enterprises in the construction of a federally-funded transit system. The Surface Transportation Assistance Act of 1978 made such percentage goals for minority business participation an absolute condition precedent to the receipt of federal funds. See 825 F.2d at 325, 331.
. The value of the license and other assets of WHCT was appraised three times at an average value of $6,520,000. The purchase price, however, was only $3,100,000.
. The need for case-by-case consideration to ensure that participants are truly disadvantaged is highlighted by the groups, in addition to blacks, who are included as "minorities” under the distress sale policy. They include those of Hispanic Surnamed, American Eskimo, Aleut, American Indian and Asiatic American extraction. 1978 Policy Statement, 68 F.C.C.2d at 980 n. 8. It should be obvious that the scope of the problem for each of these groups will "vary from market area to market area.” See Croson, at -, 109 S.Ct. at 719.
.The Court has not yet found it necessary specifically to address appropriate criteria for determining membership in a preferred minority group or class. Indisputably, millions of Americans, not generally thought by their fellows to be minorities, carry some percentage of minority blood and genes. When the preference for minority status is as economically valuable as here, is it not inevitable that some who can make a case for membership in a minority group will assert such claims despite relative affluence or good fortune? (In India, false claims of "untouchable” status, which can give access to jobs and university places, are apparently a serious problem. See Greenawalt, Judicial Scrutiny of "Benign" Racial Preference in Law School Admissions, 75 Colum.L.Rev. 559, 572 n. 84 (1975)). It simply cannot be that
. The race-neutral measures to which the dissent refers — equal employment opportunity rules and ascertainment policies — were not designed to deal with the most significant barriers to minority ownership — lack of information and financing. Compare dissent at 947 with id. at 937. I thus disagree with the dissent’s conclusion that race-neutral methods to address these entry barriers have been found wanting. See id. at 948.
.A nonminority may be eligible to buy a station at a distress sale price only if the revocation hearing involves bankruptcy or disability. If, as in this case, those particular issues are not implicated, only minority-controlled enterprises are eligible as buyers if the licensee elects to pursue a distress sale. The state of the record makes it difficult for me even to guess at the extent to which nonminorities are excluded, except to say that it is potentially limitless and completely within the control of the FCC. It is, after all, the FCC’s exercise of discretion that determines which and how many licenses are designated for revocation hearing, which and how many renewal applications are designated for noncomparative hearing, and which issues are to be heard.
. The incumbent also has the considerable advantage of being a known quantity, ordinarily one with a record of proven performance, while the challenger usually has to rely on projections and promises. See Central Florida Enterprises, 683 F.2d at 507.
. It is also suggested, dissent at 952, that if Shurberg had conveyed management and control of his company to a qualified minority and retained only a financial interest then that new organization would have been permitted to bid for the station. For that matter he could also have invested in CBS stock or moved to New York and sought a broadcast license there. I fail to see how any of these possible alternatives affect his constitutional claim.
. In addition, the FCC seeks to rationalize its minority distress sale policy with the distinct goal of promoting diversity of ownership without regard to diversity of programming. In its policy statements, the FCC has contended that diversity of ownership is a goal that in and of itself justifies racial preferences. 1978 Policy Statement, 68 F.C.C.2d at 981. Economic diversity of ownership may well be part of the "public interest” that the Commission is authorized to promote. I do not doubt that the Commission may limit multiple ownership so as to diversify control of the public airwaves. But a desire to prevent concentration of ownership cannot justify diversification along racial lines. By itself, racial diversity of ownership is conceptually no different from racial balance in the workplace.
. Justice O’Connor did make reference to the diversity rationale in her concurring opinion in Wygant, 476 U.S. at 286, 106 S.Ct. at 1853, but her opinion for the Court in Croson suggests that she would not consider promotion of racial diversity a sufficient justification for a racial set-aside. See Croson, at -, 109 S.Ct. at 721. Justice Stevens does appear to have endorsed Justice Powell’s discussion in Bakke. See Croson at - n. 1 109 S.Ct. at 733 n. 1 (Stevens, J., concurring).
. Even under Justice Stevens' broader view of acceptable governmental interests, I doubt whether the FCC’s policy is legitimate. The melting pot notion, which Justice Stevens expressed in Wygant and reiterated in Croson, suggests that "one of the most important lessons that the American public schools teach is that the diverse ethnic, cultural, and national backgrounds that have been brought together in our famous ‘melting pot’ do not identify essential differences among the human beings that inhabit our land.” Wygant, 476 U.S. at 313-15, 106 S.Ct. at 1867-68 (Stevens, J., dissenting) (quoted in Croson, at -, 109 S.Ct. at 733 n. 2 (Stevens, J., concurring)). Unlike the state's goal in Bakke, which arguably served to break down racial and ethnic stereotypes, the FCC’s policy does not reinforce the "melting pot” because television viewers never have any knowledge of the race or ethnicity of the various station owners.
. Were I free to reach the question anew, I would find the analogy wanting. It is simply unacceptable, in my view, to say that the government has a role in educating the general public through television broadcasts that is parallel to its interest in promoting diversity in the educational setting. That is a somewhat Orwellian notion. Through public education, the government has assumed a special function in preparing our youth for participation in society. Justice Powell reasoned that because "[t]he atmosphere of ‘speculation, experiment and creation’ " is “so essential to the quality of higher education,” a university has a compelling interest in ensuring that students are exposed to a diverse group of peers during their formative years. 438 U.S. at 312, 98 S.Ct. at 2759. But there is no indication that Justice Powell contemplated that his reasoning would extend beyond the distinctive context of education where the state legitimately engages in a form of indoctrination. Indeed, Justice Powell indicated that the state’s interest in fostering diversity is stronger when students are younger:
It may be argued that there is greater force to these views at the undergraduate level than in a medical school where the training is centered primarily on professional competency. But even at the graduate level, our tradition and experience lend support to the view that the contribution of diversity is substantial.
Id. at 313, 98 S.Ct. at 2760 (emphasis added).
. The FCC did not entirely repudiate this position in its Winter Park brief, but it came close by defending its preference scheme in a comparative license procedure as a constitutionally sound method of "achieving the compelling government interest — diversity of programming.” The FCC also praised its policy implicated in Winter Park as a "structural method[ ]” designed to "avoid[ ] government intrusion into regulation of program content.”
. I do not reach the question of whether the broadcast media continue to possess unique qualities sufficient to justify content regulation. I note the FCC’s inconsistency on the need for content regulation only because it undermines the "compelling need” of the agency's diversity-based rationale for the distress sale policy. The dissent argues that the 1987 continuing resolution, which prohibited the FCC from reconsidering the distress sale policy, takes precedence over the FCC’s decision to discontinue the fairness doctrine and renders the FCC’s inconsistency unimportant. The continuing resolution, however, can hardly be characterized as a “congressional determination that the public need for diversity in programming still warrants affirmative protection.” Dissent at 944 n. 25. Congress made no factual findings whatsoever concerning the existence or nonexistence of diverse programming in 1987.
. The dissent terms the distress sale policy "thoughtfully conceived and monitored,” dissent at 934, yet there is no evidence that once a sale was concluded the FCC made even the slightest effort to monitor the new station’s contribution to minority programming.
. Once again, I am obliged to point out the FCC’s brief in Winter Park offers only scanty evidence in support of the existence of such a nexus.
. Ironically, the FCC itself formerly took the position that minority preferences should be granted only after the minority applicant demonstrated a nexus to program diversity, but it was ordered by this court to assume that minority ownership would foster program diversity. TV 9, Inc. v. FCC, 495 F.2d 929, 937-38 (D.C.Cir.1973), cert. denied, 419 U.S. 986, 95 S.Ct. 245, 42 L.Ed.2d 194 (1974); Garrett v. FCC, 513 F.2d 1056, 1062-63 (D.C.Cir.1975); see Notice of Inquiry, MM No. 86-484, 52 Fed.Reg. at 596 (1987). Our decision in TV 9, which did not involve a constitutional question and was rendered before any of the Supreme Court’s affirmative action decisions, offered no support for such a nexus. Its only authority for the proposition that ownership influences content was a citation to commentary which conceded that "the proposition does not lend itself to empirical analysis,” and, in any event, only addressed whether diversity would be enhanced by increasing the number of owners (thereby minimizing concentration of ownership) not whether the race of an owner somehow affected programming content. TV 9, 495 F.2d at 938 n. 31; see Note, Media and the First Amendment in a Free Society, 60 Geo.LJ. 871, 896, 1006 (1972).
. The dissent complains that Congress is "between a rock and a hard place,” dissent at 946, because, on the one hand, it cannot under the First Amendment directly ensure a certain kind of programming or viewpoint diversity, and, on the other hand, the distress sale policy violates the Fifth Amendment because there is no evidence that the policy will ensure diverse programming. The rock and the hard place hardly seem so ominous, however, when one realizes that they are actually two constitutional provisions. It may simply be that diversity of programming is not a sufficient basis to justify this racial preference, because ensuring diverse content of radio broadcasts is not a permissible goal under the First Amendment, much less a compelling governmental interest under the Fifth. The apparent implication of Chief Judge Wald's reasoning is that Congress and the FCC may indirectly do what the First Amendment prevents them from doing directly in order to justify a plan that would otherwise violate the Fifth Amendment.
. As noted above, see supra note 32, the FCC originally insisted on a case-by-case determination as to whether a minority owner would enhance programming diversity, but was ordered by this court, without supporting evidence, to assume that nexus. See TV 9, Inc. v. FCC, 495 F.2d 929, 937-38 (D.C.Cir.1973), cert. denied, 419 U.S. 986, 95 S.Ct. 245, 42 L.Ed.2d 194 (1974); Garrett v. FCC, 513 F.2d 1056, 1062-63 (D.C.Cir.1975). In an unfortunate parody of reasoning, Congress apparently relied on the TV 9 decision, and its progeny in the FCC and this court, to document the disputed nexus.
. The dissent mistakenly suggests that I have adopted the approach of Justice Stevens’ dissenting opinion in Fullilove. Dissent at 940 & n. 15. My concern is not that "judicial review should include a consideration of the procedural character of the decisionmaking process.” Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 551, 100 S.Ct. at 2812 (Stevens, J., dissenting). That contention has been properly rejected by this court. National Treasury Employees Union v. Devine, 733 F.2d 114, 117 n. 8 (D.C.Cir.1984). The problem with Congress’ "findings" on the nexus between diversity of ownership and diversity of programming is not that they were made without adequate deliberation but that Congress did not have before it the kind of "direct evidence” that provided an “abundant historical basis" for the set-aside plan in Fullilove. 448 U.S. at 478, 100 S.Ct. at 2774 (opinion of Burger, C.J.). Indeed, Congress did not even purport to rely on any evidence.
. For a telling analytical parallel, see Comment, FCC Minority Distress Sale Policy: Public Interest v. The Public’s Interest, 1981 Wisc.L.Rev. 365, 389 (”[B]y approving the assignee ... solely on the basis of its minority ownership and basic qualifications, the Commission does a great disservice to its ultimate goal of increasing diversity of programming.”).
. This is in contrast to the manner in which minority status is taken into account in comparative licensing hearings. As noted, supra at 908 n. 6, I offer no opinion on the constitutionality of minority preference schemes in comparative licensing procedures such as those at issue in Winter Park, which are called into question by recent Supreme Court cases. But even in West Michigan, we upheld the constitutionality of the FCC's comparative evaluation process largely because "it explicitly provides for examination of a wide variety of traits to assess an applicant's potential for increasing diversity and quality of programming." 735 F.2d at 615. Race is also only a partial determinant in the random selection alternative provided for by Congress in the 1982 amendments to the Communications Act of 1934. See 47 U.S.C. § 309(i) (1982).
. When discussing the distress sale policy’s effect on nonminorities, the dissent states that “no pre-determined number of stations is reserved exclusively for minority ownership.” Dissent at 948. However, a specific, albeit random, group of licenses are set aside: all those placed in designated-for-hearing status. Analytically, there is little difference between a specific number being set aside and a specific group being set aside for minority-use only insofar as the set-aside has an impact on nonminorities. In either case, nonminorities are absolutely barred from bidding on some predetermined number of licenses. Whether that number is calculated by percentage or by fortuity — all those stations which are designated for hearing — is of no moment.
.The congressional action is especially troubling because it prevented the FCC from complying with a direct order of this court to resolve the issues described in its Notice of Inquiry concerning the justification for the distress sale policy. The continuing resolution commanded that no funds shall be used "to continue a reexamination of” the distress sale policy, and the Senate Appropriations Committee explicitly directed the FCC "to resolve within 60 days all proceedings that have been remanded by the court of appeals ..., including Shur-berg, ... in a manner consistent with the policies that mandated incentives for minorities and women in broadcast ownership.” S.Rep. No. 182, 100th Cong., 1st Sess. 77 (1987). By its action, not only has Congress prevented the FCC from attempting to muster factual support for a position that it conceded was impermissible on the present record, but it has placed the FCC in a situation where it was obligated to disregard an order of this Court. Congress’ action thus carries serious constitutional implications, because there is little difference between stripping a court of jurisdiction and stripping the Executive Branch or an independent agency of authority to comply with orders of the court. Cf. United States v. Klein, 80 U.S. (13 Wall.) 128, 145, 20 L.Ed. 519 (1872) (Congress exceeds power under exceptions clause when "language of the [statute] shows plainly that it does not intend to withhold jurisdiction except as means to an end.”); Ex Parte McCardle, 74 U.S. (7 Wall.) 506, 19 L.Ed. 264 (1869).
. It is the impossibility of retroactive effect that renders the continuing resolution irrelevant to this litigation. Congress might be able to dictate a new rule for prospective application to a pending dispute. See Multi-State Communications, Inc. v. FCC, 728 F.2d 1519 (D.C.Cir.1984). In saying that I "dismiss) ] the entire episode,” dissent at 946, my colleague apparently overlooks the distinction between prospective and retroactive effect.
Concurrence Opinion
(concurring in judgment):
Alan Shurberg and Shurberg Broadcasting Company of Hartford, Inc. (Shurberg) petition for review of the decision of the
I. Facts
Prior to 1977 Faith Center, Inc. (Faith Center) held licenses in various cities to operate three television stations and one FM station. However, Faith Center solicited funds that were not used for the purpose described in its broadcasts which re-suited in the revocation of all its licenses except WHCT-TV in Hartford, Connecticut whose license had been designated for revocation hearing. The first two attempts by Faith Center to make distress sales of WHCT-TY failed due to the minority purchasers’ inability to obtain financing. After these two failed attempts, Shurberg attempted to have an open comparative hearing but his petition was denied by the FCC. Subsequently, the Hartford station and license were transferred to Astroline in a non-competitive proceeding pursuant to the Commission’s distress sale policy which promotes minority participation in the ownership of broadcast properties.
That none of the funds appropriated by this Act shall be used to repeal, to retroactively apply changes in, or to continue a reexamination of, the policies of the Federal Communications Commission with respect to comparative licensing, distress sales and tax certificates granted under 27 U.S.C. 1071, to expand minority and women ownership of broadcasting licenses, including those established in Statement of Policy on Minority Oownership of Broadcast Facilities, 68 F.C.C.2d 979 and 69 F.C.C.2d 1591, as amended 52 R.R.2d 1313 (1982) [sic4] and Mid-Florida Television Corp., 60 F.C.C.2d 607 Rev. Bd. (1978) [sic5], which were effective prior to September 12, 1986, other than to close MM Docket No. 86-484 with a reinstatement of prior policy and a lifting of suspension of any sales, licenses, applications, or proceedings, which were suspended pending the conclusion of the inquiry....
On February 9, 1988 the FCC issued an Order in Faith Center, Inc. BC Docket No. 80-730 which included the following:
In compliance with this litigation [set forth above], the Commission has ordered MM Docket No. 86-484 closed, thereby terminating the reexamination of its licensing policies based on racial, ethnic or gender preferences. Order, FCC 88-17, adopted January 14, 1988. In order to comply with the legislation fully, the Commission also ordered that its licensing policies based on racial, ethnic or gender preferences that were in effect prior to September 12, 1986, be reinstated and that the presiding Administrative Law Judges, the Review Board, and the Office of the General Counsel process all licensing cases in a manner consistent with Commission policy in effect prior to September 12, 1986. Id4
The FCC then denied Shurberg’s application for a comparative hearing and Shur-berg now seeks review by this court of the Commission’s Order. Shurberg complains of being denied a comparative hearing, alleges that ex parte contacts tainted the validity of the proceedings, and attacks the Commission’s application of its minority distress sale policy to him. However, the case has leveled down to a constitutional attack on the distress sale policy.
II. Constitutional Analysis
As others have noted,
Some broad settled principles can be sifted from the Court’s decisions on minority preference programs. First, “benign” racial or ancestoral distinctions are given the same standard of review as invidious classifications. Croson, — U.S. at -, 109 S.Ct. at 721 (O’Connor, J.), 109 S.Ct. 735 (Scalia, J.). Wygant, 476 U.S. at 273, 106 S.Ct. at 1846; Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 491, 100 S.Ct. at 2781 (Burger, C.J.); Bakke, 438 U.S. at 291-299, 98 S.Ct. at 2748-53 (Powell, J.).
The two contentions asserted in support of the constitutionality of the Commission’s distress sale policy are that it remedies past societal discrimination and promotes programming diversity. Dissent op. 939, 952.
A. The Untailored Effect
The distress sale program is not only not “narrowly tailored,” it is a completely un-tailored program. That is, the program is open-ended in that circumstances may cause it to be applied to any broadcast licensee without regard to any past discrimination and thereby deprive all nonminorities of their right to equal access to a broadcast license. The FCC program thus denies the equal protection of the law to innocent nonminorities.
The licenses of thirty-eight stations have been subjected to the minority distress sale program.
This case presents a good example of a license becoming subject to the minority distress sales program independent of any past discrimination. Here, Faith Center was alleged to have fraudulently solicited funds by not using the funds for the stated purpose in violation of 18 U.S.C. § 1343. 82 F.C.C.2d 1 (1980), reconsid. denied, F.C.C. 81-235 (1981), aff'd mem., Faith Center Inc. v. FCC, 679 F.2d 261 (1982), cert. denied, 459 U.S. 1203, 103 S.Ct. 1188, 75 L.Ed.2d 435 (1983). There is no connection between Faith Center’s violation and any past discrimination that is in any way related to the number of licenses which may become available to minorities under the distress sale program. Although, in practice, only a small number of licenses have been transferred pursuant to the policy, there is no actual limitation, in theory or in practice, on the number of licenses that may be so transferred. Nor is there any requirement that the offense of the licensee be in any way related to any act of unlawful discrimination. The distress sale program bears no relationship to any alleged past discrimination and, therefore, violates the Croson majority position that:
[Bjecause racial characteristics so seldom provide a relevant basis for disparate treatment, and because classifications based on race are potentially so harmful to the entire body politic, it is especially important that the reasons for any such classification be clearly identified and unquestionably legitimate.
Croson at -, 109 S.Ct. at 727, quoting Fullilove, supra, 448 U.S. at 533-35, 100 S.Ct. 2903-04 (Stevens, J., dissenting) (footnotes omitted).
Likewise, because the distress sale program has no limits of any character it is not sufficiently tailored to the goal of promoting programming diversity. Compliance is voluntary and the program contains no assurance that any programming diversity will be achieved.
The Silberman opinion also contends that the distress sale program, as a means of
In stating that the 1987 Senate Committee Report was merely assertive, the Silber-man opinion is certainly correct. However, the Report also made reference to H.R.Rep. No. 765, 97th Cong., 2d Sess., 40 (1982), which clearly, and at some length, detailed the support for the legislative conclusion that there was a nexus between minority ownership and programming diversity. H.R.Rep. at 42.
As a remedy of past discrimination and a means to promote diversity, the minority distress sale program unduly burdens innocent nonminorities. It operates so as to necessarily impact on a discrete class of nonminorities — i.e., every nonminority applicant for a broadcast license in a particular market that is designated for revocation hearing. The effect of this FCC program is particularly damaging because it removes the opportunity to obtain a license in a competitive market that is unlikely to be repeated.
The dissent asserts that since Shurberg did not have a vested ownership interest in the station, he lacked a reasonable expectation of acquiring any license and hence cannot succeed in a constitutional attack on the policy. Dissent at 951-52. This is peculiar reasoning. In my view the fact that he is a valid applicant denied a hearing to his damage permits him to successfully attack the unconstitutional character of the denial. The dissent analogizes the distress sale program to an affirmative action hiring plan as opposed to a firing plan. Justice Powell’s Wygant opinion expressed a preference for remedying employment discrimination through hiring plans because they diffused the burden of a race conscious program throughout society instead of disrupting the expectations of a small group with an established interest. 476 U.S. at 282, 106 S.Ct. at 1851.
The dissent’s analysis is unpersuasive. While the minority preference plan does not neatly fit into Justice Powell’s dichotomy of hiring and firing plans outlined in Wygant, the program operates more like a firing plan in that it imposes its burden squarely on a small group of innocent people, like Shurberg, denying them a unique and tangible benefit — the opportunity to compete for a broadcast license that would normally under applicable decisions, the statute and rules be open to a comparative hearing. Communications Act of 1934, 47 U.S.C. § 309(e), amended; Ashbacker Radio Corp. v. FCC, 326 U.S. 327, 330, 66 S.Ct. 148, 150, 90 L.Ed. 108 (1945).
The dissent also argues that the distress sale program does not unduly burden non-minorities because it affects only a fractional percentage of broadcast licenses. Dissent at 952. This argument is a nonstarter because regardless of the impact of the program on the entire market, the burden of hopefully correcting some discrimination and achieving some diversity in programming falls largely on Shurberg in this case and will necessarily exclude every nonminority individual in every distress sale. These burdened individuals are entitled to the equal protection guaranteed by the Fifth Amendment even though constitutional violations by the program have not yet reached substantial proportions. Supra, n. 2.
Conclusion
The FCC minority distress sale program thus deprives Alan Shurberg and Shurberg Broadcasting of their equal protection rights under the Fifth Amendment. The program is not narrowly tailored to remedy past discrimination or to promote programming diversity because it unduly burdens Shurberg, an innocent nonminority, and is not reasonably related to the interest it seeks to vindicate.
For the foregoing reasons I join in the judgment of the court, that the minority distress sale program denies Shurberg equal protection under the due process clause of the Fifth Amendment.
.The FCC’s distress sale policy to promote Minority Ownership of Broadcasting Facilities, 68 F.C.C.2d 979, as expanded and reaffirmed in 1982 provides:
The distress sale policy allows broadcasting licensees whose licenses have been designated for revocation hearing, prior to the commencement of a hearing, to sell their station to a minority-owned or controlled entity, at a price “substantially” below its fair market value. A licensee whose license has been designated for hearing would ordinarily be prohibited from selling, assigning or otherwise disposing of its interest, until the issues have been resolved in the licensee's favor. Thus, extension of the tax certificate and distress sale policies fosters minority ownership by providing broadcast licensees with an incentive to transfer their interests to minority-owned or controlled entities. Id., at 851.
In the Matter of Commission Policy Regarding the Advancement of Minority Ownership in Broadcasting, 92 F.C.C.2d 849, 861. The stated objective was to increase diversity programming to serve First Amendment principles and to reflect minorities’ tastes and viewpoints. Id. at 850. The Commission also reported:
Since 1978, we have approved 27 distress sales and 55 tax certificates,* which have contributed significantly to increased minority ownership in broadcasting.... [The amendment of the] distress sale policy marks a departure from our long established practice of prohibiting a licensee in a renewal or revocation hearing from disposing of its interests prior to the resolution of issues in its favor.
* Tax certificates authorized by 26 U.S.C. § 1071 permit sellers of broadcast properties to defer capital gains taxation on a sale whenever the sale was “necessary or appropriate to effectuate a change in a policy or the adoption of a new policy by the Commission with respect to the ownership and control of radio broadcasting stations ...” The policy arose originally in connection with divestitures imposed by the Commission’s multiple ownership rules.
Id. at 852, 858.
The 1978 policy statement requiring the distress sale price to be substantially below its fair market values was expanded in 1980 to limit the licensee’s recovery to not more than 75% of the station’s fair market value. Lee Broadcasting Corp., 76 F.C.C.2d 462 (1980).
. Bolling v. Sharpe, 347 U.S. 497, 74 S.Ct. 693, 98 L.Ed. 884 (1954).
. See n. 1. Since its adoption in 1978, 38 distress sales have been approved by the Commission and the overall effort of fostering minority ownership has been moderately successful. See Distress Sales Approved, copies available from FCC Consumer Assistance and Small Business Division, Office of Public Affairs (updated October 18, 1988). Astroline states that the number of minority controlled stations acquired by all means has nearly doubled from less than one (1) percent in 1977 to now close to two (2) percent of all broadcast properties licensed by the Commission. (Astroline Brief, p. 5, n. 3).
. The congressional ban on reexamination of the FCC's distress sale policy was reenacted in 1988. 134 Cong.Rec. S-10,004 (Daily ed. July 7, 1988).
. See, Silberman, at 910. Dissent at 934.
. Johnson v. Transportation Agency, 480 U.S. 616, 107 S.Ct. 1442, 94 L.Ed.2d 615 (1987), is not strictly applicable to the constitutional analysis that is required here. Johnson is a Title VII case which expressly recognized that Title VII analysis differs from constitutional analysis. 480 U.S. at 627-28 n. 6, 107 S.Ct. at 1449-50 n. 6. However, applying Johnson's Title VII requirements, which are analogous to constitutional analysis required here, the FCC’s minority distress sale program is flawed. In Johnson, the Transportation Agency implemented an affirmative action program in which the sex of a job applicant could only be taken as one factor in an employment decision, and the Court relied heavily on the fact that, under the program, sex or race was considered as a mere plus factor in the evaluation process:
[T]he Plan merely authorizes that consideration be given to affirmative action concerns when evaluating qualified applicants.... [T]he Agency Plan requires women to compete with all other qualified applicants. No persons are automatically excluded from consideration; all are able to have their qualifica*929 tions weighed against those of other applicants.
Johnson, 480 U.S. at 638, 107 S.Ct. at 1455 (emphasis in original).
The FCC’s minority distress sale program works precisely to the opposite end since it takes a broadcast license completely out of the normal competitive licensing process and all nonminority individuals, Shurberg included, are automatically excluded from competing. The minority’s status here is not merely a small plus factor. Rather, it is the determinative factor that deprives all nonminorities of any opportunity to compete. Thus, the virtues Justice Brennan found in the narrowly tailored Transportation Agency Plan point out the vices in the untailored FCC minority distress sale program.
. Choper, Continued Uncertainty as to the Constitutionality of Remedial Racial Classifications: Identifying the Pieces of the Puzzle, 72 Iowa L.Rev. 255 (Jan. 1987).
. As stated in Croson: “[T]he mere recitation of a "benign’ or legitimate purpose for a racial classification, is entitled to little or no weight.” Croson at -, 109 S.Ct. at 724. (Citing Weinberger v. Wiesenfeld, 420 U.S. 636 at 648, n. 16, 95 S.Ct. 1225 at 1233, n. 16, 43 L.Ed.2d 514 (1975) which, as here, involved the due process clause of the Fifth Amendment.). Thus, there is no difference, in this respect, between pronouncements of "benign” purpose by Congress or state legislatures.
. The Supreme Court has not explicitly held that a race conscious program aimed at promoting diversity must be structured to minimize the burden on innocent nonminorities. It is quite difficult, however, to conclude that the Court would not impose such requirement where the constitutional right to equal protection is involved. The best explanation for the Court's failure to so act is that Justice Powell’s opinion in Bakke is the only prior consideration given to the issue as to whether promoting diversity is a justification for a race conscious program. Consequently, the Court has not had the occasion to develop or apply the narrowly tailored doctrine explicitly to promoting diversity. Because the minority distress sale policy imposes the same injury on innocent nonminorities regardless of whether the justification asserted for the affirmative action program is to promote diversity or to remedy past discrimination, it is logical that the no undue burden test would apply with equal force in both cases.
.The dissent in n. 46 recognizes "that Faith Center’s misconduct was unrelated to racial discrimination. [And then asserts] [S]urely this can make no difference.” But it does. It points out that this award does not even remedy one instance of racial discrimination. While it is not required that the "resources themselves must be the product of past discrimination," if they had been, the minority distress sale program would have remedied some identifiable past discrimination, but not even that justification exists here. The minority distress sale program presents opportunities that are not dependent on any past discrimination — societal or specific. Therefore, the program bears no relationship to the asserted governmental interest in remedying past discrimination as required by Fullilove. 448 U.S. at 514-15, 100 S.Ct. at 2793 (Powell, J.).
.The question of whether promoting programming diversity and remedying societal discrimination constitute compelling government interests need not be reached here. In City of Richmond v. Croson Co., supra, Justice O’Connor’s plurality opinion held open the possibility that Congress, pursuant to its power under Section 5 of the 14th Amendment, may legislate race-conscious programs on grounds which the several states may not. Croson at -, 109 S.Ct. at 720. Justice Kennedy’s concurrence, however, pointedly challenged Justice O'Connor's assertion that Congress may legislate to remedy society discrimination and noted that such a case "is not before us, any reconsideration of that issue must await some further case.” Croson, at -, 109 S.Ct. at 734 (Kennedy, J.).
On the issue of promoting programming diversity, the dissent and Judge Silberman have some disagreement. In Bakke, Justice Powell held that promotion of diversity in the school/university context constituted a compelling state interest. 438 U.S. at 311-313, 98 S.Ct. at 2759-60 (Powell, J.). Outside of past governmental discrimination, the Court has not recognized any other governmental interest as compelling. Yet, as the dissent observes, Justice O’Connor's Wygant opinion explicitly holds open the possibility that “lower courts” could rely on other interests sufficiently compelling "to sustain the use of affirmative action policies.” Wygant, 476 U.S. at 286, 106 S.Ct. at 1853 (O’Connor, J.). The dissent contends that this Circuit's holding in West Michigan Broadcasting v. FCC, 735 F.2d 601, 614-15 (D.C.Cir.1984), recognized the promotion of programming diversity as an interest sufficiently compelling to "sustain the use of affirmative action policies" and this court is bound by West Michigan. Dissent at 941. Judge Silberman reluctantly accepts the holding in West Michigan that programming diversity constitutes a compelling state interest. He considers such contention to be “a somewhat Orwellian notion.” Silberman, J. at 920, n. 27. In this context, it is significant to note that Justice O'Connor’s Croson plurality opinion indicates that racial classifications should be "strictly reserved for remedial settings” in order to avoid fueling racial animosities. Croson at-, 109 S.Ct. at 721 (O'Connor, J.). This case does not involve a “remedial setting.”
Because the minority distress sale program is not narrowly tailored, it is not necessary in this opinion to reach the question whether either promoting programming diversity or remedying societal discrimination are a sufficiently compelling governmental interest to support the use of government sponsored minority preference programs.
. See Distress Sales Approved, copies available from FCC Consumer Assistance and Small Business Division, Office of Public Affairs (updated October 18, 1988).
. See RKO General, Inc. v. FCC, 670 F.2d 215 (D.C.Cir.1981) (license renewal denied for corporate misconduct).
. Greater Boston Television Corporation v. FCC, 463 F.2d 268 (D.C.Cir.1971) (license renewal denied for improper ex parte contacts).
.The dissent contends that objecting to the minority distress sale program on the grounds that there is no limit to the number of licenses the program may reach is "perverse” in light of the relatively few distress sales over the previous ten years. Dissent at 950 n. 40. This attack misses the thrust of the argument; the lack of numerical limits on the program is but one aspect of the untailored nature of the minority distress sale policy. In addition to the lack of any numerical limit on the program, there is no limitation whatsoever as to the value, size or market share of affected stations, or the need for prior discrimination by the licensee. In this way, the program is untailored in any respect and completely obliterates the constitutional rights of all nonminorities seeking a license. It never places minority status as merely one plus factor for the Commission to weigh in licensing as Johnson v. Transportation Agency, 480 U.S. 616, 107 S.Ct. 1442, 94 L.Ed.2d 615 (1987), did in employment. Rather minority status is elevated to the determinative factor.
. All distress sales of broadcast licenses must be approved by the FCC.
. The classification of American Eskimos, Aleuts and Hispanic sumamed individuals as minorities who have been discriminated against in the broadcast licensing field cannot be said to be unquestionably legitimate. "The gross over-inclusiveness of Richmond’s [the FCC’s] racial preference strongly impugns the ... claim of remedial motivation." Croson at -, 109 S.Ct. at 728. See infra, at 933 n. 26.
. The dissent states that the small number of distress sales are insufficient to provide empirical data as to whether proper programming diversity is achieved. Dissent at 946. In my view, the small number of distress sales provides a perfect group for such study.
. Supra, at 927-28.
. The Report of the Appropriations Committee states:
The Congress has expressed its support for (minority preference) policies in the past and has found that promoting diversity of ownership of broadcast properties satisfies important public policy goals. Diversity of ownership results in diversity of programming and improved service to minority and women audiences.
S.Rep. No. 182, 100th Cong., 1st Sess. 76 (1987).
. The Report of the Senate Appropriations Committee cites H.R.Conf.Rep. No. 97-765, 97th Cong., 2d Sess. 37-44, 1982, as authority for its assertion that Congress in the past supported minority preference programs for the broadcasting industry. S.Rep. No. 182, 100th Cong., 1st Sess. 76-77 (1987). The cited House Conference Report (1982) is replete with statements outlining its finding that minority preference programs in broadcast licensing promotes diversity in programming. For example, the Report states: “The nexus between diversity of media ownership and diversity of programming services has been repeatedly recognized by both the Commission and the courts." H.R.Conf.Rep. No. 765, 97th Cong., 2d Sess. at 40 (1982). My personal view, which is identical to that asserted by the FCC brief in Steele v. FCC, No. 84-1176, discussed below, is that, while undoubtedly there may be some exceptions, market forces largely predominate programming — but the congressional finding controls.
Judge Silberman relies on the FCC’s brief in Steele as support for his assertion that there is no nexus between minority ownership and programming diversity. Silberman op., at 922-23. The FCC Steele brief states:
No record has ever been developed to support the critical, underlying assumption upon which this preference scheme is necessarily based — that the racial or gender characteristics of a station’s [sic] owner will have a significant effect on a station's programming. FCC Steele brief at 22.
The brief concluded that "market forces are now and will continue to be, principally responsible for providing diversity of programming and viewpoint." Id. at 22-23. The congressional finding, however, eclipses the FCC’s argument in Steele and the FCC’s brief in Winter Park Communications v. FCC, Nos. 85-1755 and 85-1765, appears to repudiate its Steele brief. In Winter Park, the Commission states that its minority preference policy on the competitive licensing process promotes diversity as minority ownership enhances "the public's exposure to significant, diverse groups that make up the nation.” FCC Winter Park brief at 30.
. Fullilove at 473, 100 S.Ct. at 2772. Chief Justice Burger, speaking in a minority preference case, remarked: A congressional program choice or finding does not “render it (the program) immune from judicial scrutiny."
. TAN 5.
. The dissent “acknowledge^” at p. 948 that the minority distress sale program acts to "reserve certain opportunities to minority purchasers alone” and thus, “more closely resembles” the university admissions plan struck down in Bakke, rather than a "plus factor” scheme the Court has approved of in other contexts. See, Bakke, 438 U.S. at 316-19, 98 S.Ct. at 2761-63; Johnson v. Transportation Agency, 480 U.S. 616, 637-39, 107 S.Ct. 1442, 1455-56, 94 L.Ed.2d 615 (1987) (under Title VII analysis).
. Since the FCC implemented the minority distress sale program in 1978, eleven applications for license or license renewals were denied by the Commission. As of Fiscal Year 1987, the FCC licensed 11,493 broadcast stations, 9,847 of which were commercial stations. See, Federal Communications Commission 53rd Annual Report/Fiscal Year 1987, p. 21, 36-37. Additionally, the FCC Report notes that there are 1,489 translator and booster FM stations, and 5,568 translator and low power television stations which are subject to minority preference programs. Id. at 20-21.
. The FCC’s 1978 Statement of Policy on Minority Ownership of Broadcasting Facilities defines the groups recognized as having minority status for purposes of the distress sale program as follows: "Black, Hispanic Surnamed, American Eskimo, Aleut, American Indian and Asiatic American Extraction.” 68 F.C.C.2d at 781, n. 8 (1978).
. Section 309(e) provides, in part, that upon the Commission finding that a licensee has violated FCC rules, shall: ”[F]ormally designate the application [of the licensee] for hearing on the ground or reasons then obtaining and shall notify the applicant and all other known parties in interest of such action_ Any hearing subsequently held upon such application shall be a full hearing in which the applicant and all other parties in interest shall be permitted to participate.”
. The stakes to the parties involved are certainly substantial. If Shurberg eventually prevails, he will be awarded a license for a station appraised at $6,520,000; if the FCC prevails, Astro-line will preserve a $3,420,000 subsidy and Faith Center will salvage $3,100,000 from its lost license.
. President John F. Kennedy.
Dissenting Opinion
dissenting:
Congress, governmental agencies, and federal courts have struggled for nearly two decades to define the constitutional limits on affirmative efforts to improve access of minority groups to the mainstream of American life. This case involves a unique type of governmental access program not heretofore passed on by the Supreme Court. The majority’s invalidation of the Commission’s ten-year old minority distress sale program in my view impermis-sibly overturns a considered congressional judgment as to the appropriate means of assuring diversity of viewpoint over the national airwaves. In casting off a thoughtfully conceived and monitored program aimed at attaining a legitimate con-gressionally mandated end, the majority has too rigidly applied Supreme Court affirmative action guidelines designed for other types of programs, ignored firm precedents in this circuit, and failed to credit the explicit intent of Congress.
I. The Constitutional Status of Government-Sponsored Minority PREFERENCE PROGRAMS
The United States Supreme Court has issued four decisions concerning the constitutional limitations on voluntary government-sponsored affirmative action programs. See Wygant v. Jackson Board of Education, 476 U.S. 267, 106 S.Ct. 1842, 90 L.Ed.2d 260 (1986); Fullilove v. Klutznick, 448 U.S. 448, 100 S.Ct. 2758, 65 L.Ed.2d 902 (1980); Regents of the University of California v. Bakke, 438 U.S. 265, 98 S.Ct. 2733, 57 L.Ed.2d 750 (1978); City of Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co., — U.S. -, 109 S.Ct. 706, 102 L.Ed.2d 854 (1989).
Within this circuit, moreover, a third interest has been recognized as sufficiently compelling to justify the use of racial preferences. In West Michigan Broadcasting Co. v. FCC, 735 F.2d 601 (D.C.Cir.1984), cert. denied, 470 U.S. 1027, 105 S.Ct. 1392, 84 L.Ed.2d 782 (1985), this Court upheld the use of race in comparative licensing procedures as part of the Commission’s effort “to obtain a diverse mix of broadcasters.” 735 F.2d at 613. That decision, of course, is binding precedent except insofar as it is called into question by subsequent decisions of the Supreme Court.
[Although its precise contours are uncertain, a state interest in the promotion of racial diversity has been found sufficiently “compelling,” at least in the context of higher education, to support the use of racial considerations in furthering that interest ... And certainly nothing the Court has said today necessarily forecloses the possibility that the Court will find other governmental interests which have been relied upon in the lower courts but which have not been passed on here to be sufficiently “important” or “compelling” to sustain the use of affirmative action policies.
Wygant, 476 U.S. at 286, 106 S.Ct. at 1853 (O’Connor, J., concurring) (citations omitted) (emphasis added).
The Supreme Court’s recent decision in Croson imposed stringent requirements on state and local governments seeking to institute affirmative action programs for the purpose of providing increased economic opportunities for minorities. Croson, however, differs from the present case in two fundamental respects. First, Croson involved the initiative of a local governmental body, while continued enforcement of the distress sale policy has been mandated by an Act of Congress. Second, the distress sale policy was intended by Congress to enhance public access to diverse broadcast programming — a goal that is quite different from that which the Court addressed in Croson. We must therefore bear in mind that the limitations announced in that decision cannot be applied mechanically to the present controversy. Rather, we must carefully analyze the objective the distress sale policy serves, and the constitutional fit of the chosen means to that end, bearing in mind Congress’ repeated authorization and endorsement of this program’s specific method and goal.
In 1965, the FCC
It was not inconsistent with [the Communications Act of 1934,] therefore, for the Commission to conclude that the maximum benefit to the “public interest” would follow from allocation of broadcast licenses so as to promote diversification of the mass media as a whole.
... “The ‘public interest’ standard necessarily invites reference to first amendment principles” ... and, in particular, to the First Amendment goal of achieving “the widest possible dissemination of information from diverse and antagonistic sources.”
FCC v. National Citizens Committee for Broadcasting [NCCB], 436 U.S. 775, 795, 98 S.Ct. 2096, 2112, 56 L.Ed.2d 697 (1978) (citations omitted).
The Commission found achievement of its goal of viewpoint diversity through ownership diversity hampered by the dearth of minority broadcasters. As a result of the “exhaustively documented” un-derrepresentation in the ownership of mass media broadcast facilities, West Michigan, 735 F.2d at 603 n. 5, the FCC expanded its diversification policy to encompass a positive effort at attaining minority representation in broadcasting:
Full minority participation in the ownership and management of broadcast facilities results in a more diverse selection of programming. In addition, an increase in ownership by minorities will inevitably enhance the diversity of control of a limited resource, the spectrum.
Statement of Policy on Minority Ownership of Broadcasting Facilities, 68 F.C.C.2d 979, 981 (1978) [hereinafter 1978 Policy Statement].
In implementing its policy of diversity of viewpoint through diversity of ownership, the FCC designed the distress sale program as part of a broader strategy for dealing with the “extreme disparity between the representation of minorities in our population and in the broadcasting industry.” 1978 Policy Statement at 982.
Administrative law judges had previously been instructed to award a competitive preference to minority license applicants in comparative hearings if the minority owners would actively participate in running the station. Several pending license applications involving a significant minority ownership interest had been expedited. Minority underrepresentation persisted, however, and the FCC’s Minority Ownership Taskforce, after careful study, identified the cause in several structural impediments to minority access to broadcasting facilities.
The Minority Ownership Taskforce concluded that the most significant barriers to minority ownership were lack of knowledge of stations up for sale, attributable largely to an “old-boy network” monopoly on such information, and the unavailability of adequate financing for potential minority owners. See Minority Ownership Taskforce Report, supra, at 9, 11. Lack of broadcasting experience among potential minority applicants, an inevitable concomitant of persistent underrepresentation in the industry, also blocked their access. As long as these formidable impediments to entry existed, the Taskforce felt that the market would not self-correct so as to afford adequate opportunities for minority ownership.
Responding to the Taskforce Report, the FCC decided that it must deal directly with the identified entry barriers — lack of information and financing. It announced policies to grant capital gains tax deferral certificates to those selling to minority firms
On several occasions Congress has endorsed the FCC’s efforts to diversify media control through programs to encourage minority ownership and control.
[An] important factor in diversifying the media of mass communications is promoting ownership by racial and ethnic minorities —groups that traditionally have been extremely underrepresented in the ownership of telecommunications facilities and media properties. The policy of encouraging diversity of information sources is best served by not only awarding preferences based on the number of properties already owned, but also by assuring that minority and ethnic groups that have been unable to acquire any significant degree of media ownership are provided an increased opportunity to do so.
Id. at 43 (emphasis added).
Congress again reaffirmed its strong support for the FCC’s programs to foster minority ownership in 1987. In its appropriations law for 1988, Congress prohibited repeal or reconsideration of the distress sale policy and two other minority preference programs. Pub.L. No. 100-202, 101 Stat. 1329 (1987).
The Congress has expressed its support for such policies in the past and has found that promoting diversity of ownership of broadcast properties satisfies important public policy goals. Diversity of ownership results in diversity of programming and improved service to minority and women audiences.
S.Rep. 182, 100th Cong., 1st Sess. 76 (1987) (emphasis added). The discourse at the hearings with then-FCC Chairman Fowler made clear the Committee’s view that “the Commission [has] a responsibility to make sure that [the airwaves] are used to reflect the diversity of views and the diversity of background and interests in our country.” Departments of Commerce, Justice, State, the Judiciary and Related Agencies Appropriations for Fiscal Year 1988: Hearings on H.R. 2763 Before a Subcommittee of the Senate Committee on Appropriations, 100th Cong., 1st Sess. 17 (1987) (statement of Senator Lautenberg) [hereinafter 1987 Hearings\
III. Analysis
A. Scope of Review
Whatever its status at prior stages of this litigation, the distress sale program is today a deliberately chosen congressional policy, embodied in legislation passed by the House and Senate and signed by the President. In my view, the distress sale policy is a constitutional means of pursuing Congress’ objective: ensuring greater diversity in programming. As Judge Silber-man recognizes, “the breadth of discretion in the choice of remedies may vary with the nature and authority of a governmental
Noting that the 1987 statute forbade the Commission to reexamine the distress sale policy, and thus precluded compliance with our previous remand order, Judge Silber-man suggests that the statute impermissi-bly constricted the jurisdiction of the court of appeals. See Silberman op. at 925 n. 39. The statute, however, says nothing about jurisdiction: it simply directs the agency to apply a particular rule of law to disputes before it. Congress plainly has the power to establish substantive rules to be applied in agency adjudications; moreover, Congress may insist that a new rule be applied to a pending dispute. See Multi-State Communications, Inc. v. FCC, 728 F.2d 1519 (D.C.Cir.1984).
Nor did the statutory change work any unjust surprise on the parties to this case. The 1987 statute did change the applicable law, since it eliminated the agency’s prior discretion to abrogate or modify the distress sale policy. The statute did not, however, require that the rights of Shurberg or Astroline be adjudicated on the basis of standards which were unforeseen at the time this dispute began. To the contrary, the law by its terms required only that the agency continue to apply its preexisting rules. It therefore seems clear to me that this is not a case in which the application of a new statute to a pending proceeding will create “manifest injustice” to the litigants.
It is true that courts must act cautiously in interpreting appropriations measures, to avoid inferring substantive effects that were never intended. However, the Supreme Court has never suggested that this principle of statutory construction should be transformed into a rigid constitutional mandate, requiring courts to make a qualitative determination whether each house has given a measure sufficient consideration before voting in favor of it. Such an intrusion into Congress’ legislative deliberations would pose serious separation-of-powers problems, and neither the language nor logic of the Constitution compels such an inquiry.
733 F.2d at 117 n. 8 (emphasis in original) (citation omitted).
B. The Distress Sale Policy as a Means of Increasing Diversity in Programming
1. The Compelling Nature of the State Interest
To this point the Supreme Court has identified two governmental interests that may, under appropriate circumstances, be sufficiently compelling to justify the use of racial preferences: remedying past discrimination and enhancing diversity in higher education. Moreover, the governmental interest asserted here — the desire to ensure that television viewers have access to a diverse range of programming — seems closely analogous to the educational interest with Justice Powell found sufficient in Bakke.
The question presented here — whether the government’s interest in educational diversity is closely analogous to its interest in preserving public access to a variety of broadcast fare — is admittedly a question on which reasonable people may differ. And it is a question to which the Supreme Co ,.rt has thus far failed to provide a definitive answer. It is not, however, an open question within this circuit. This court expressly approved the analogy in West Michigan, stating that “[j]ust as the FCC rests its goal of attaining diverse programming on the First Amendment value ‘that the widest possible dissemination of information is essential to the welfare of the public,’ Justice Powell recognized that a state university could find support in the First Amendment for the goal of attaining a diverse student body_” 735 F.2d at 614 (citation omitted). The law within this circuit is that broadcaster diversity, like diversity within public institutions of higher education, is a sufficiently compelling governmental interest to justify the use of racial preferences. This precedent may legitimately be disregarded only if it has been undermined by subsequent decisions of the Supreme Court.
Judge Silberman contends that Wygant undermines the authority of West Michigan, since in his view the Wygant Court rejected the “role model” theory offered by the Jackson Board of Education. See Sil-berman op. at 922. In fact, however, only four Justices in Wygant rejected the role model theory; Justice White’s concurrence focused exclusively on the fact that the plan involved layoffs.
Judge Silberman also suggests that the Court in Croson rejected the pursuit of diversity as a permissible justification for affirmative action programs. My colleague relies heavily on the Croson plurality’s insistence that racial preferences should be “strictly reserved for remedial settings.” 109 S.Ct. at 721 (Opinion of O’Connor, J.);
Even if I read the Croson plurality as eliminating the diversity rationale as a permissible justification for state and local affirmative action programs, I would not conclude that the same restrictions should apply to Congress. The plurality’s recognition of the broad remedial powers of Congress — in particular, its recognition that “Congress may identify and redress the effects of society-wide discrimination,” see 109 S.Ct. at 719 — militates against any easy transference of the limitations deemed appropriate for state and local entities. Because the Croson Court did not directly address the permissibility of the diversity rationale, and because that case dealt with the remedial powers of a local government rather than with the authority of Congress, I do not believe that Croson requires the rejection of the federal interest asserted here.
Certainly the state lacks the power to exercise day-to-day control over the pro
Of course, to say that Congress has a legitimate interest in enhancing broadcast diversity does not mean, ipso facto, that the state’s interest is sufficiently compelling to justify the use of a racial preference. And I recognize that Justice Powell’s Bakke opinion focused on the distinctive characteristics of the academic environment. For those who are fortunate enough to attend a college or university, interaction with fellow students may be a principal means of access to information about the world.
Even if this were an open question within the circuit, I would therefore conclude that the promotion of broadcast diversity is a compelling governmental interest, an interest closely analogous to the enhancement of diversity within the educational institutions operated by the state. For good or ill, a large portion of the American polity relies upon the broadcast media as a principal source of information about the world in which they live. Given the governmental role in selecting broadcast licensees, I believe that the state bears a responsibility
Judge Silberman mixes apples and oranges in claiming that the FCC’s abandonment of the fairness doctrine indicates that the enhancement of diversity on the airwaves is no longer a compelling interest. See Silberman op. at 921. The fairness doctrine, whatever its merits, is quite distinguishable from the distress sale policy: the fairness doctrine involved direct control over the content of programming. The distress sale policy, by contrast, seeks to diversify programming indirectly through a limited targeting of license opportunities. The FCC did not abandon the fairness doctrine because it believed that fostering debate on controversial issues of public importance was not part of its mission, but rather because it considered the means involved to be content-based control of speech.
I cannot accept my colleague’s denigration of the state interest involved here. In my opinion the government clearly has a compelling interest, sufficient to justify the careful use of racial preferences, in encouraging the dissemination of broadcast programming which reflects the nation’s diversity. This view is compelled by circuit precedent and is fully consonant with the decisions of the Supreme Court.
2. The Nexus Between Ownership and Programming
Judge Silberman is openly skeptical about the effectiveness of any FCC policy that addresses program or viewpoint diversification through broadening ownership or control of the media. Of course, there is no guarantee that minority ownership and management will necessarily lead to minority-oriented programming or even to the expression of a discrete minority viewpoint on the airwaves. Similarly, there is no guarantee that minority students will intermingle with nonminority students or exchange viewpoints in a state university, or even that the particular minority students admitted will have typical or distinct “minority” viewpoints. Cf. Bakke, 438 U.S. at 311-13, 98 S.Ct. at 2759-60. These are predictive judgments of a sort which simply do not lend themselves to ironclad proof. It seems to me entirely foreseeable, however, that minority broadcasters — like minority students — will have distinct perspectives to convey. And it seems equally foreseeable that these perspectives will find expression in the licensee’s program
The ownership-programming nexus underlying the distress sale policy does not, however, rest on such assumptions alone, but on two decades of congressional, judicial and agency findings. Back in 1968, the Kerner Commission announced:
The media report and write from the standpoint of a white man’s world. The ills of the ghetto, the difficulties of life there, the Negro’s burning sense of grievance, are seldom conveyed. Slights and indignities are part of the Negro’s daily life, and many of them come from what he now calls the “white press” — a press that repeatedly, if unconsciously reflects the biases, the paternalism, the indifference of white America. This may be understandable, but it is not excusable in an institution that has the mission to inform and educate the whole of our society.
Report of the National Advisory Commission on Civil Disorders 203 (1968). Nine years later, the United States Commission on Civil Rights endorsed the Kerner Commission’s view “that a mass medium dominated by whites will ultimately fail in its attempts to communicate with an audience that includes blacks.”
Several decisions of this court have also been premised on the reasonable belief that encouraging minority ownership can be expected to promote diversity of programming. See, e.g., West Michigan, supra; Garrett v. FCC, 513 F.2d 1056 (D.C.Cir.1975); TV 9, Inc. v. FCC, 495 F.2d 929 (D.C.Cir.1973), cert. denied, 419 U.S. 986, 95 S.Ct. 245, 42 L.Ed.2d 194 (1974); Citizens Communications Center v. FCC, 447 F.2d 1201 (D.C.Cir.1971), clarified, 463 F.2d 822 (D.C.Cir.1972). Indeed, we have held that “it is upon ownership that public policy places primary reliance with respect to diversification of content, and that historically has proven to be significantly influential with respect to editorial comment and the presentation of news.” TV 9, 495 F.2d at 938. I believe that these principles remain valid today.
Congress’ conclusions about the nexus between minority ownership and programming diversity, however, are the most significant, for, as the Supreme Court has instructed us, the showing necessary to support an affirmative action program depends in part on the competence of the governmental unit making the finding. As early as 1982, Congress recognized the minority-ownership/diversity nexus, which is the basis for the distress sale policy. H.R. Conf.Rep. No. 765, 97th Cong., 2d Sess. 40 (1982) (“[t]he nexus ... has been repeatedly recognized”). In authorizing a lottery system for choosing among qualified broadcast license applicants, Congress directed the FCC to implement a minority-ownership preference, so that “this approach to enhancing diversity through such structural means will in turn broaden the nature and type of information and programming disseminated to the public.” Id. at 43.
In 1987, Congress spoke even more clearly, directly addressing the distress sale policy itself. The FCC had proposed to Congress a “one-time study designed to elicit empirical evidence to determine whether there is a nexus between minority/female ownership and viewpoint diversity as required by the Constitution....” 1987 Hearings, supra, at 77 (statement of Commissioner Fowler). Congress’ response was that further study was unwarranted; the tie between minority ownership and programming diversity was sufficiently strong to support the constitutionality of the distress sale policy. “The committee believes the inquiry is unwarranted.... Diversity of ownership results in diversity of programming.” S.Rep. No. 182, 100th Cong., 1st Sess. 76 (1987). The Act itself
The evidence supporting these findings has typically been anecdotal rather than statistical. Cf. 1985 Fairness Report, 102 F.C.C.2d 143 (1985) (FCC’s belief that the fairness doctrine chilled speech is justified by reference to anecdotal rather than statistical evidence). In part this is because the subject does not lend itself to quantification. In part, though, it is because the dearth of minority broadcasters has made it quite difficult to draw empirical conclusions concerning the programming offered by minority-owned stations. Judge Silber-man’s approach to the case places Congress in an impossible bind; it makes the distress sale policy’s constitutionality dependent on evidence which simply will not be available until minority ownership of broadcast stations has increased substantially.
Judge Silberman fails as well to take account of the first amendment limits placed upon Congress and the FCC, which preclude more direct efforts to enhance program diversity. Although the Commission cannot control directly the variety of programming that licensees afford the public, Judge Silberman nonetheless insists that the constitutionality of this congres-sionally mandated policy requires demonstrable proof of the connection between ownership and programming. Congress is between a rock and a hard place: it cannot under the first amendment directly ensure a certain kind of programming or viewpoint diversity, yet the panel overturns its entirely reasonable efforts aimed at diversity for want of proof that they will definitely produce the anticipated results.
I also do not believe that the distress sale policy is rendered invalid by- the fact that participating minority broadcasters are not required to prove that they are individual victims of prior discrimination. See Silber-man op. at 915-16. Three Justices in Cro-son did stress the desirability of such fine-tuning, see 109 S.Ct. at 718 (Opinion of O’Connor, J.), but in no case has a majority of the Court held that individualized consid
In fact, the promotion of minority ownership as an approach to program diversity clearly meets the test of “narrow tailoring.” The FCC has, over the years, experimented with several devices to further program diversification without directly regulating programming content. The distress sale policy was adopted only after specific findings by the FCC that equal employment opportunity rules
The history of the FCC’s efforts in this field thus demonstrates that the distress sale policy was adopted only after other means had proven unsuccessful in enhancing minority access to the mass media.
3. The Significance of Racial Diversity
The most problematic feature of the distress sale policy lies in the fact that its benefits are bestowed solely upon minority buyers. The distress sale policy is not a setaside: no pre-determined number of stations is reserved exclusively for minority ownership. It must nevertheless be acknowledged that distress sales reserve certain opportunities to minority purchasers alone, and that the Commission’s approval or rejection of a proposed sale will be made without considering the qualifications of nonminority competitors. The plan therefore more closely resembles the admissions program struck down in Bakke, rather than the Harvard Plan, noted approvingly in Justice Powell’s opinion, which provided that minority status would be an advantage but would not be an absolute requirement for any admissions slot.
To begin with, it should be noted that Justice Powell was the only member of the Bakke Court who perceived a constitutional distinction between an affirmative action plan which reserved a specified number of slots for minority candidates and a plan which employed race as a plus-factor in admissions decisions. The other four Justices who reached the constitutional question expressly denied that any such constitutional distinction exists. See Bakke, 438 U.S. at 378-79, 98 S.Ct. at 2793 (Opinion of Brennan, White, Marshall, and Blackmun, JJ.). Furthermore, subsequent decisions of the Supreme Court have made it clear that the Constitution does not prohibit every affirmative action plan which reserves particular opportunities exclusively for minority applicants.
Fullilove, after all, upheld a plan which reserved a specified percentage of government business for minority contractors. Justice Powell voted to sustain the plan, and the basis on which he distinguished the case from Bakke is highly instructive. Justice Powell did not rely on a distinction between affirmative action plans designed to promote diversity and plans intended to remedy prior discrimination. Rather, he emphasized the broad powers of Congress: “I [do not] conclude that use of a set-aside always will be an appropriate remedy or that the selection of a set-aside by any other governmental body will be constitutional [citing Bakke ]. The degree of specificity required in the findings of discrimination and the breadth of discretion in the choice of remedies may vary with the nature and authority of a governmental body.” Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 515-16 n. 14, 100 S.Ct. at 2793-94 n. 14 (Powell, J., concurring).
Nor do the Court’s opinions in Wygant support the proposition that Judge Silber-man advances today. The Court struck down the challenged affirmative action plan, with Justices Powell, O’Connor, and White writing opinions in support of the judgment. No Justice suggested, however, that the Wygant plan could be invalidated solely on the ground that it employed a numerical formula to determine the portion of the teaching staff to be reserved for minorities. In more recent cases involving court-ordered remedies for specific discriminatory practices, the Court has upheld the use of numerical quotas where less severe steps have proven unavailing. See supra 934 n. 1.
In light of subsequent decisions, I read Bakke to hold, at most, that an affirmative action plan which uses a “plus-factor” approach is preferable to a plan reserving specified opportunities for minorities, if the two plans will be equally effective in achieving their remedial goals. In the present case, however, I believe that there are ample grounds for concluding that a plan utilizing a “plus-factor” approach would not be sufficient. The dramatic statistical underrepresentation of minorities noted by the FCC and Congress, see Minority Ownership Taskforce Report (Commission in 1978 notes one percent minority ownership); 1987 Hearings at 17 (Congress noting “mere 2 percent” ownership) (statement of Sen. Lautenberg), underscores why policies aimed merely at encouraging general diversity have proven inadequate. The Commission’s general pursuit of diversified broadcasting has failed miserably in achieving meaningful minority representation. 1978 Policy Statement, supra, at 980, 982. Significantly, the FCC made no similar findings of underrepresentation of various “professions” or “religions,” which Judge Silberman groundlessly claims are equally good targets for a diversity preference. See Silberman op. at 921. A narrowly focused program is justified both by the particular importance of racial equality and by the lack of success of less carefully targeted efforts.
It is also important to point out that the FCC has simultaneously followed the “plus-factor” approach to licensing by affording enhancement credits for minority ownership and management in comparative hearings. Both Congress and the FCC, however, have found that this technique alone simply does not do the job:
*950 It is clear that the current comparative hearing process has not resulted in the award of significant numbers of licenses to minority groups. Many minority applicants are simply unable to participate in comparative hearings which often take a considerable period of time and require substantial economic resources.
H.R.Conf.Rep. No. 765, 97th Cong., 2d Sess. 44 (1982) (emphasis added). Thus, where diversity of ownership has not proven practically attainable through a multi-factored evaluation of the “total” applicant, as may work in student admissions, it does not seem unreasonable to target previously identified financial barriers to minority access.
C. Effect Upon Nonminority Applicants
Past Supreme Court decisions, as the majority points out, have evaluated affirmative action schemes by assessing the burdens they impose on innocent nonminorities. Those burdens have been measured in different ways. In Fullilove, for example, the Chief Justice, in finding the 10% minority set-aside for construction contracts constitutional, focused on its relatively small impact on total procurement opportunities. See Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 484-85 & n. 72, 100 S.Ct. at 2777-78 & n. 72 (Opinion of Burger, C.J.).
These standards, it seems to me, recognize two distinct ways in which an affirmative action plan may be said to impose excessive burdens on innocent nonminorities. The Fullilove standard focuses on the burden placed on nonminority applicants as a group: the statistical inquiry ensures that minorities will not be allocated an exorbitant portion of the opportunities in a given sphere. The Wygant standard focuses on the burdens imposed on particular nonminority individuals. The distress sale policy satisfies both these standards.
The distress sale policy imposes minimal burdens on nonminority license applicants as a group. By its very terms, it may be invoked at the Commission’s discretion only with respect to a small fraction of all broadcast licenses (those designated for revocation or renewal hearings on the basis of basic qualification issues), and only when the licensee chooses to sell out at a distress price rather than go through with the hearing. Unlike the University of California admissions plan found unconstitutional in Bakke, 438 U.S. at 289, 98 S.Ct. at 2747 (Opinion of Powell, J.), no specific number of licenses is set aside for allocation to minorities through the distress sale mechanism. Instead, the distress sale policy merely offers an alternative and largely unpredictable procedural route for license applications. The circumstances in which distress sales arise are rare and only a small number are approved; as of the briefing of this case, the distress sale policy had resulted in the transfer of only thirty-three stations to minority-controlled businesses in seven years. These distress sales represent 0.28% of all broadcast stations in the United States,
Thus, the distress sale policy imposes far less severe burdens upon nonminorities as a group than did Fullilove’s MBE set-aside. As in Fullilove, nonminority firms remain free to compete for the vast majority of licensee opportunities available. Furthermore, even when the Commission considers a distress sale, it does not refuse to entertain nonminority petitions for access to the license in question. Interested non-minority parties can oppose both the licensees’ election of the distress sale procedure and the specific transaction proposed to the Commission. “A distress sale ... is a form of extraordinary relief and depends on the facts and circumstances of the individual petition.” Faith Center, Inc., 82 F.C.C.2d 1, 35 (1980).
Nor does the distress sale policy impose an unacceptable burden on particular non-minority individuals such as Shurberg. The Supreme Court has looked most skeptically at affirmative action programs involving layoffs because firings inevitably involve a greater disruption of settled expectations. See Wygant, 476 U.S. at 282-83, 106 S.Ct. at 1851 (Opinion of Powell, J.) (“Denial of a future employment opportunity is not as intrusive as loss of an existing job”).
Plainly the distress sale policy imposes disadvantages on innocent nonminority applicants, and I do not intend to belittle their hardships. A broadcast license is a valuable property; only a few become available; and the licenses are not fungible.
It should also be noted that neither Shur-berg nor any other nonminority applicant is denied financial participation in enterprises that qualify for distress sale treatment by reason of the racial composition of their owners or managers. As a matter of fact, in order to lessen the financial obstacles to increased minority ownership, the FCC will accept applications for sales to limited partnerships, in which management and control reside primarily with qualified minority general partners but substantial financial rewards flow to nonminority limited partners who have provided the necessary capital. See 1982 Policy Statement, supra, at 853-55.
D. Remedying Past Discrimination
As I noted earlier, see supra, pp. 941-43, it is somewhat deceptive to speak of a sharp distinction between the government’s desire to promote broadcast diversity and its desire to remedy past discrimination. Certainly it is appropriate to distinguish between the attempt to further public access to varied programming and the attempt to advance the economic interests of minority broadcasters. But the effort to promote broadcast diversity is itself, in a broad sense, a “remedial” program: it seeks to address the lasting effects of our nation’s long history of racial discrimination. I will acknowledge, however, that the term “remedial” is sometimes used (as Judge Silberman uses it, see Silberman op.
The Court in Croson, while sharply limiting the power of state and local governments to institute affirmative action programs, acknowledged the expansive authority of Congress to mandate racial preferences. Justice O’Connor’s plurality opinion recognized that “Congress may identify and redress the effects of society-wide discrimination,” 109 S.Ct. at 719; see also id. at 736-37 (Scalia, J., concurring). The three dissenters, who would extend broad remedial authority to other public entities, would surely not deny it to Congress. I read Croson as reaffirming a broad congressional authority to employ race-based remedies to ameliorate the position of previously disadvantaged racial groups. Congress is not restricted to addressing problems caused by its own prior discrimination, nor is it required to identify particular instances of discrimination as a predicate for remedial action.
In the present case, I have focused exclusively on the goal of enhancing broadcast diversity. This is because Congress, in mandating continued implementation of the distress sale policy, relied exclusively on the diversity rationale. There is simply no indication that Congress was motivated, even in part, by a desire to improve the lot of minority broadcasters. My emphasis on the diversity rationale in this case should not, however, obscure my strong conviction that Congress retains broad authority to employ race-based measures in other areas to enhance the economic situation of those who have previously been the victims of lasting and pervasive discrimination.
IV. Conclusion
The majority has struck down a program mandated by Congress, one that is part of a broader and constantly evolving effort to ensure diversity in programming through diversity in ownership. The congressional decision was hardly an uninformed choice: Congress acted on the basis of nearly a decade of experience with the distress sale policy. Judge Silberman’s principal error lies in his failure to give due weight to the considered judgment of Congress. That error is compounded by his denigration of the public interest in programming diversity and his failure to fully credit the precedents of this circuit.
Congress, despite the agency’s misgivings, has ordered the continuation of a limited minority access scheme designed to promote diversification in broadcasting through the elimination of identified structural barriers that have traditionally burdened minority ownership. Its distress sale policy is narrowly tailored to address the critical entry barriers to minority participation in media ownership while imposing only minimal burdens on innocent third parties. I do not believe that so modest and targeted a program furthering such a compelling aim violates the Constitution. I therefore respectfully dissent.
. See also Local 28 of the Sheet Metal Workers’ Int'l Ass’n v. EEOC, 478 U.S. 421, 106 S.Ct. 3019, 92 L.Ed.2d 344 (1986) (court-ordered plan directed at employment discrimination); United States v. Paradise, 480 U.S. 149, 107 S.Ct. 1053, 94 L.Ed.2d 203 (1987) (same).
. This court’s decision in West Michigan antedated the Supreme Court’s decisions in Wygant and Croson, and of course West Michigan is no longer binding insofar as it conflicts with the higher Court’s pronouncements. I do not believe, however, that either Wygant or Croson undermines our earlier views concerning the compelling nature of the state’s interest in broadcasting diversity. See infra, pp. 941-43.
I also recognize that the distress sale policy differs in significant respects from the use of race as one element in comparative licensing proceedings. See infra, pp. 948-50. Both policies, however, start from the premise that broadcast diversity is a sufficiently compelling state interest to justify the use of racial preferences.
. Appellant argued strenuously before this court that the FCC, in this case, did not follow its own distress sale policy rules and exceeded permissible limits on its discretion to apply the policy in the licensing process. Indeed, in granting Faith Center a third successive opportunity to arrange a distress sale rather than requiring a renewal hearing, the FCC acknowledged that its balancing of the public interest in minority-ownership policies against the public interest in permitting comparative hearings was a "close ques
I note in passing my disagreement with Judge Silberman’s contention, see Silberman op. at 908 n. 7, that I would not be entitled to address the constitutional question if I did not adopt the FCC’s position on the statutory issue. Since a majority of the panel has determined that the constitutional question must be resolved, I reserve my right to express my views, whether or not I would have reached the issue if the choice were mine alone to make.
. In the Communications Act of 1934 Congress empowered the FCC to allocate broadcast licenses in such a way as to serve the "public convenience, interest, or necessity.” 47 U.S.C. § 307(a).
. The FCC also reiterated its earlier concern that “diversification ... is additionally desirable where a government licensing system limits access by the public to the use of radio and television facilities.” 1978 Policy Statement, supra, at 981 (quoting 1965 Policy Statement, supra, at 394).
. The FCC had previously noted that "[djespite the fact that minorities constitute approximately 20 percent of the population, they control fewer than one percent of the 8500 commercial radio and television stations currently operating in this country." FCC Minority Ownership Task-force, Minority Ownership in Broadcasting 1 (1978) [hereinafter Minority Ownership Task-force Report ] (emphasis in original).
. The FCC has the authority under § 1071 of the Internal Revenue Code to grant sellers tax certificates to defer capital gains taxation on the transaction. These certificates may be used as incentives to induce sales of broadcast properties to minority owners. See 26 U.S.C. § 1071; Issuance of Tax Certificates, 19 Rad.Reg. 2d (P & F) 1831 (1970).
. The distress sale policy is essentially an administrative exception to the general rule that once a licensee’s basic qualifications have been called into question by designation for either a revocation or a renewal hearing, the licensee may not voluntarily transfer the license. There have, however, always been exceptions to this rule for bankrupt or disabled licensees. The minority distress sale policy expanded these exceptions to include licensees who would agree to sell at a discount to qualified minority-controlled purchasers.
By 1982, the FCC had approved only 27 distress sales in four years. Finding that the continued underrepresentation of minorities was still a “serious concern” and financing still posed "the single greatest obstacle” to increased minority participation, the FCC modified the distress sale policy further. After reviewing the recommendations of its Advisory Committee on Alternative Financing for Minority Opportunities in Telecommunications, the Commission announced that it would authorize distress sales to limited partnerships so long as the general partner was a member of a minority group and owned more than 20% of the enterprise. The purpose of the amendment was to allow minority entrepreneurs easier access to the necessary capital. See Commission Policy Regarding the Advancement of Minority Ownership in Broadcasting, 92 F.C.C.2d 849, 855 (1982) [hereinafter 1982 Policy Statement].
In 1985, the FCC began consideration of a further revision of the distress sale policy to allow a licensee to exercise a distress sale option at a later stage in the renewal proceeding. See Notice of Inquiry, 50 Fed.Reg. 42,047 (1985). Nonetheless, in the past six years, the Commission has only approved 11 more distress sales, for a modest total of only 38 in ten years.
.The distress sale policy requires that the sale price reflect no more than 75% of the market value of the broadcast property and license in order to retain the deterrent effect of license revocation hearings. See Lee Broadcasting Corp., 76 F.C.C.2d 462 (1980). Nonetheless, the prospect of even greater loss if a license is revoked gives the current licensee an economic incentive to sell at this discount price to a minority buyer.
. "It is the firm intent of the Conferees that traditional Commission objectives designed to promote the diversification of control of the media of mass communications be incorporated in the administration of a lottery system.” H.R. Conf.Rep. No. 765, 97th Cong., 2d Sess. 40 (1982).
. The congressional ban on FCC reconsideration of these programs was recently extended through fiscal year 1989. See Pub.L. No. 100-459, 102 Stat. 2186, 2216-17 (1988).
. The application of Fullilove to this case is complicated by the fact that in Fullilove — as in Bakke and Wygant — no opinion commanded a majority of the Court. I rely principally on Chief Justice Burger’s opinion, joined by Justices Powell and White. The Chief Justice’s opinion plainly occupied a middle ground between the position of Justices Brennan, Marshall, and Blackmun, who announced fairly deferential standards for review of affirmative action programs generally, and that of Justices Stewart, Rehnquist, and Stevens, who would have struck down the MBE program.
. I note that Judge MacKinnon accepts the premise that the distress sale program represents a considered congressional policy choice. See MacKinnon op. at 932-33.
The fact that Congress has acted does not, of course, mean that the distress sale policy is ipso facto constitutional. My colleagues are correct in asserting that even an Act of Congress is subject to searching scrutiny when constitutional values are implicated. See Silberman op. at 923-24; MacKinnon op. at 932-33. But while the congressional judgment is not dispositive, it surely makes a difference. Congress has far broader powers than does an administrative agency; its findings of fact are entitled to greater respect; and, unlike the agency, it need not compile a formal record or issue an opinion. Moreover, section 5 of the fourteenth amendment entrusts Congress with the authority to implement equal protection guarantees. These factors do not obviate the need for judicial review, but they do shape the contours of our inquiry.
.Although Congress was evidently aware of Shurberg’s pending complaint, there is no suggestion that Shurberg was singled out for unfavorable treatment or that the congressional action was in any sense a vendetta against a particular individual. This case is thus plainly distinguishable from News America Publishing, Inc. v. FCC, 844 F.2d 800 (D.C.Cir.1988), which stressed that “[t]he Hollings Amendment strikes at Murdoch with the precision of a laser beam” and that "Murdoch and News America were more than mere ‘catalysts’ for congressional action aimed at a particular evil.” Id. at 814, 815.
. Judge Silberman’s approach, in fact, is strikingly similar to that of Justice Stevens in Fulli-love. Since Justice Stevens’ approach was accepted by no other member of the Supreme Court, we are powerless to adopt it here.
. One commentator has written that "[b]ecause [legislators] are the direct representatives of the people, the law imposes no restrictions on them with respect to their use or nonuse of facts as a basis for legislating.” Davis, Facts in Lawmaking, 80 Colum.L.Rev. 931 (1980). And Judge Silberman has cited no authority for the proposition that a court may scrutinize the decision-making process of Congress and invalidate laws to which "inadequate” attention has been paid.
.Moreover, Congress had acted some years previously to mandate the use of racial preferences within the FCC’s lottery system. I do not contend that the lottery mechanism is constitutionally indistinguishable from the distress sale program. Both, however, depend on the same core premises: that a station’s programming will be significantly affected by the race of its owner, and that the public interest in diverse programming is served by measures which increase the heterogeneity of broadcast licensees.
. Justice White stated that “[w]hatever the legitimacy of hiring goals or quotas may be, the discharge of white teachers to make room for blacks, none of whom has been shown to be a victim of any racial discrimination, is quite a
. The statement in Croson that racial classifications should be "strictly reserved for remedial settings," 109 S.Ct. at 721, represents the view of only four Justices and is therefore not a holding of the Court.
. I must acknowledge that Justice Stevens, like Judge Silberman, appears to read Justice O'Con-nor’s opinion as rejecting the diversity rationale. See 109 S.Ct. at 730 & n. 1 (Stevens, J., concurring).
. Under Judge Silberman’s view of Croson, all consideration of race by public universities as an element of diversity would be rendered unconstitutional. Moreover, all nine Justices in Bakke agreed that Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. § 2000d, imposes restrictions at least as stringent as those established by the Constitution. See Bakke, 438 U.S. at 286-87, 98 S.Ct. at 2746 (Opinion of Powell, J.); id. at 328-40, 98 S.Ct. at 2767-73 (Opinion of Brennan, White, Marshall, and Blackmun, JJ.); id. at 416, 98 S.Ct. at 2812 (Opinion of Stevens, J.). Judge Silberman’s prohibition, therefore, would perforce apply to all private universities which receive federal funds. I would hesitate, however, to infer such a sweeping change in the law governing university admissions policies based on a few ambiguous words of dicta in a plurality opinion.
. A university is not, however, a self-contained world: University students have access to the same range of broadcast fare (and often to cable services) which is available to the public generally. If the university has a compelling interest in exposing students to diverse ideas in addition to those which are available to the citizenry at large, then it is hard to see how the state could have a less weighty interest in ensuring diversity for those who lack access to university facilities.
. In Keyishian v. Board of Regents, 385 U.S. 589, 603, 87 S.Ct. 675, 684, 17 L.Ed.2d 629 (1967), the Court stated: "Our Nation is deeply committed to safeguarding academic freedom which is of transcendent value to all of us and not merely to the teachers concerned. That freedom is therefore a special concern of the First Amendment_ The Nation’s future depends upon leaders trained through wide exposure to that robust exchange of ideas which discovers truth 'out of a multitude of tongues, [rather] than through any kind of authoritative selection,’ United States v. Associated Press, 52 F.Supp. 362, 372.” The citation to Associated Press — which justified antitrust regulation of the print media as a means of enhancing diversity— at least suggests that the Court saw a connection between the government’s efforts to promote diversity of opinion inside and outside the classroom. Justice Powell quoted this passage from Keyishian in his Bakke opinion. See 438 U.S. at 312, 98 S.Ct. at 2759.
. In its decision to eliminate the fairness doctrine, the Commission was principally motivated by its doubts concerning the doctrine’s effectiveness, not by doubts as to the legitimacy of governmental efforts to enhance broadcast diversity. The Commission stated that "under the standard of review set forth in Red Lion, a governmental regulation such as the fairness doctrine is constitutional if it furthers the paramount interest of the public in receiving diverse and antagonistic sources of information. Under Red Lion, however, the constitutionality of the fairness doctrine becomes questionable if the chilling effect resulting from the doctrine thwarts its intended purpose." Syracuse Peace Council, 2 F.C.C.Rcd. 5043, 5052 (1987) (emphasis added).
In denying reconsideration of its order abrogating the fairness doctrine, the Commission stated: “As noted in the August order, the fairness doctrine is clearly a content-based regulation of broadcast speech. Neither that order nor this reconsideration calls into question the constitutionality of our content-neutral, structural regulations designed to promote diversity." Syracuse Peace Council (Reconsideration), 3 FCC Rcd. 2035, 2041 n. 56 (1988) (citation omitted).
. My colleague’s reliance on the FCC's abrogation of the fairness doctrine also ignores the fact that Congress has acted in this case. The statutory requirement that the distress sale policy be continued reflects a congressional determination that the public need for diversity in programming still warrants affirmative protection. If there were in fact a contradiction between discontinuation of the fairness doctrine and the decision to maintain the distress sale policy, this court would plainly be required to give precedence to the congressional judgment.
. The nexus is not limited to the broadcasting context, but has been documented in other communications industries as well. See, e.g., Media and the First Amendment in a Free Society, 60 Geo.L.J. 867, 896 (1972) (stating that ownership is the key variable affecting news content and editorial policy of a newspaper).
. United States Commission on Civil Rights, Window Dressing on the Set: Women and Minorities in Television 2 (1977).
. Clearly Congress had a sufficient basis for its belief that increased minority ownership of broadcasting facilities will enhance diversity of programming. In 1978, the Commission concluded "that diversification in the areas of programming and ownership — legitimate public interest objectives of this Commission — can be more fully developed through our encouragement of minority ownership of broadcast properties,” 1978 Policy Statement at 981. Four years later, recognizing "the ever-present ‘dearth of minority ownership’ in the telecommunications industry to be a serious concern,” it reaffirmed and expanded the distress sale policy and other minority ownership-oriented policies. See 1982 Policy Statement at 852. Judge Silber-man relies heavily on the Commission’s recent doubts concerning the existence of the nexus. See Silberman op. at 921 (citing FCC’s Steele Brief). Given the existence of conflicting views within the agency, it was plainly within the competence of Congress to find that the nexus exists.
Since the original congressional ban on reexamination of the distress sale policy, the Congressional Research Service has released a report which supports the conclusion that a nexus exists between minority ownership and programming. See Minority Broadcast Station Ownership and Broadcast Programming: Is There a Nexus? (Congressional Research Service 1988). Senator Hollings relied on this report in successfully arguing for a reenactment of the appropriations ban. See 134 Cong. Rec. S10.021 (daily ed. July 27, 1988).
. Because "balancing the various First Amendment interests involved in the broadcast media ... is a task of great delicacy and difficulty,” Columbia Broadcasting System, Inc. v. Democratic Nat'l Committee, 412 U.S. 94, 102, 93 S.Ct. 2080, 2086, 36 L.Ed.2d 772 (1973), Judge Silber-man’s belittlement of Congress' clearly expressed mandate is particularly inappropriate. Under such circumstances, "we must afford great weight to the decisions of Congress and the experience of the Commission.” Id.
. In the context of court-ordered race-conscious relief, six members of the Supreme Court agreed in Local 28 that "preferential relief benefiting individuals who are not the actual victims of discrimination” may be required. 478 U.S. at 482, 106 S.Ct. at 3053.
. The Supreme Court has praised the FCC’s efforts in minority employment as a way of accomplishing programming diversity. "The Federal Communications Commission has adopted regulations dealing with the employment practices of its regulatees_ These regulations can be justified as necessary to enable the FCC to satisfy its obligation under the Communications Act of 1934 ... to ensure that its licensees’ programming fairly reflects the tastes and viewpoints of minority groups.” NAACP v. FPC, 425 U.S. 662, 670 n. 5, 96 S.Ct. 1806, 1812 n. 5, 48 L.Ed.2d 284 (1976) (citations omitted).
. The FCC’s "ascertainment” policy required licensees to contact community leaders and members of the general public, specifically including minorities and women, to obtain information about community interests so as to present programming responsive to those interests. See Ascertainment of Community Problems by Broadcast Applicants, 57 F.C.C.2d 418 (1976). As part of a conscious dismantling of command and control regulations — actions requiring specific conduct by licensees — the FCC has more recently cut back on ascertainment requirements. See Honig, The FCC and Its Fluctuating Commitment to Minority Ownership of Broadcast Facilities, 27 How.L.J. 859, 867 (1984).
. In announcing the distress sale policy, the FCC concluded that “[wjhile the broadcasting industry has on the whole responded positively to its ascertainment obligations and has made significant strides in its employment practices, we are compelled to observe that the views of racial minorities continue to be inadequately represented in the broadcast media.” 1978 Policy Statement, supra, at 980 (footnotes omitted).
.The FCC cited research showing that audience survey data tends systematically to underestimate black or Spanish-speaking audiences and often fails to measure and report adequately their listening habits. See Minority Ownership Taskforce Report at 22-24 (1978). “The rating services have been accused of subjecting ethnic media to gross prejudices and generalizations. This problem has been traced, in large part, to the absence of minorities in decision-making positions with advertising agencies or the major corporate advertisers.” Id. at 25. In light of the FCC’s own doubts, Judge Silber-man’s reliance on a station owner's response to the demands of the marketplace to ensure diversity, see Silberman op. at 922, is unconvincing. The FCC's Taskforce Report rejected such reliance as unacceptable in view of its diversity mandate.
Acute underrepresentation of minorities among the owners of broadcast properties is troublesome because it is the licensee who is ultimately responsible for identifying and serving the needs and interests of his or her audience. Unless minorities are encouraged to enter the mainstream of the commercial broadcasting business, a substantial proportion of our citizenry will remain under-served and the larger, nonminority audience will be deprived of the views of minorities.
Minority Ownership Taskforce Report, supra, at 1 (emphasis added). While Judge Silberman cites the deregulatory rulemakings of the past decade to support the proposition that market forces now are sufficient to create diverse programming, see Silberman op. at 922-23 (citing the FCC’s Steele Brief), none of the cited rule-makings revisit, let alone directly call into question, the explicit findings of the Commission in its minority ownership rulings.
.Judge Silberman argues that the proliferation of new media outlets and technologies obviates the traditional "scarcity of the spectrum” rationale that supported the FCC’s diversity of programming policies. See Silberman op. at 921. Even assuming some validity to its argument, the majority never comes to grips with the failure of sheer numbers of media alone to affect the structural barriers to increased minority ownership of broadcast properties. We know already that these same barriers operate just as acutely in cable and other media as they do in radio and television. Underrepresentation of minority voices in programming is not cured by greater numbers and varieties of mass media if they continue to be controlled by nonminority enterprises. See Hammond, Now You See It, Now You Don't: Minority Ownership in an “Unregulated" Video Market Place, 32 Cath.U.L.Rev. 633, 638, 662 (1983). Underrepresentation of minority views in television is particularly troubling. The impact of television on our daily lives, and those of our children, is unquestionably greater than that of print media.
Unlike print, television does not require literacy. Unlike the movies, television is "free” ... and it is always running. Unlike the theater, concerts, movies, and even churches, television does not require mobility. It comes into the home and reaches individuals directly. With its virtually unlimited access from cradle to grave, television both precedes reading and, increasingly, preempts it.
United States Commission on Civil Rights, Window Dressing-on the Set: An Update 44 (1979) (quoting Gerber & Gross, Living With Television: The Violence Profile, 26 J.Comm. (Spring 1976) at 176).
. In fact, it would appear that the Commission’s doubts have been short-lived. As Judge Silberman acknowledges, see Silberman op. at 11, the FCC’s brief in Winter Park Communications v. FCC, Nos. 85-1755 and 85-1756 (D.C. Cir., argued Nov. 21, 1988), supports the continued use of minority preferences within the FCC’s comparative licensing procedures. Certainly the use of race in comparative hearings is distinguishable from the present case; and it is not clear whether the Commission, if given the choice, would retain the distress sale policy. Both policies, however, presume a connection between programming content and the race of a station owner; given the Commission's stance in Winter Park, it would appear that the FCC now believes that the nexus exists. In light of the Commission’s most recent pronouncements, Judge Silberman's reliance on the FCC's earlier brief in Steele, see Silberman op. at 921, 922-23, appears imprudent.
. This is also the principal distinction between the distress sale policy and the FCC’s comparative licensing procedures. The West Michigan court emphasized that comparative hearings involve "a consideration of minority status as but one factor in a competitive multi-factor selection system that is designed to obtain a diverse mix of broadcasters.” 735 F.2d at 613 (emphasis in original). The court stated, however, that "[i]n giving special weight to [this] factor[ ] we in no way imply that [it] would be essential to the constitutionality of a government affirmative action program." Id. at 614.
. The Chief Justice noted that it was "not a constitutional defect in [the minority business enterprise set-aside provision] that it may disappoint the expectations of nonminority firms,” 448 U.S. at 484, 100 S.Ct. at 2777, especially given that the 10% minimum minority participation translated into only 0.25% of the annual expenditure for construction work in the United States. Id. at 484-85 n. 72, 100 S.Ct. at 2777-78 n. 72.
. The Wygant plurality reasoned that "[i]n cases involving valid hiring goals, the burden to be borne by innocent individuals is diffused to a considerable extent among society generally. Though hiring goals may burden some innocent individuals, they simply do not impose the same kind of injury that layoffs impose." 476 U.S. at 282, 106 S.Ct. at 1851 (emphasis in original).
.See Brief amicus curiae of National Black Media Coalition, the League of United Latin American Citizens, and the NAACP, at 33 (filed July 15, 1985). The FCC also noted the small number of distress sale assignments when it recently sought comments on revising the policy. See Notice of Inquiry, 50 Fed.Reg. at 42,048 n. 6 (1985).
. The Commission, in fact, refused to allow distress sale treatment for two other Faith Center stations and nonminority firms filed applications for both licenses. Faith Center, Inc., 82 F.C.C.2d 1 (1980), recons, denied, 86 F.C.C.2d 891 (1981).
. Compare United Steelworkers v. Weber, 443 U.S. 193, 99 S.Ct. 2721, 61 L.Ed.2d 480 (1979) (holding voluntarily adopted racial quotas permissible under Title VII) and Local 93, Int’l Ass’n of Firefighters v. Cleveland, 478 U.S. 501, 106 S.Ct. 3063, 92 L.Ed.2d 405 (1986) (approving hiring and promotion preferences in consent decree) with Firefighters Local 1784 v. Stotts, 467 U.S. 561, 104 S.Ct. 2576, 81 L.Ed.2d 483 (invalidating racial quota that required layoffs).
. I recognize that Shurberg may have a difficult time acquiring another television station. In this respect, however, the distress sale policy is no different from the use of race in comparative licensing procedures, a practice which has been repeatedly upheld by this court.
. Writing for the Wygant plurality, Justice Powell noted that "[e]ven a temporary layoff may have adverse financial as well as psychological effects. A worker may invest many productive years in one job and one city with the expectation of earning the stability and security of seniority.... Layoffs disrupt these settled expectations in a way that general hiring goals do not." 476 U.S. at 283, 106 S.Ct. at 1851. Plainly Shurberg has not suffered the sort of injury which Justice Powell associated with layoffs. Justice Powell himself analogized “hiring” plans to school admissions preference schemes,
. Judge MacKinnon attaches constitutional significance to the fact that Faith Center’s misconduct was unrelated to racial discrimination. See MacKinnon op. at 931. Surely this can make no difference. When racial preferences are used in the distribution of scarce resources, the Constitution does not require that the resources themselves must be the product of past discrimination. Clearly the government contracting opportunities at issue in Fullilove did not become available because of any discriminatory act.
. Judge Silberman does not see how this alternative ”affect[s] [Shurberg’s] constitutional claim.” Silberman op. at 918 n. 23. It is obvious, however, that the distress sale policy does allow nonminorities to share in the admittedly substantial financial benefits, see Silberman op. at 916, created by a license revocation situation, see supra at 937 note 9, and thus its burden is lighter than the burden of a hypothetical program reserving all profits to minorities.
.My colleagues err in focusing only on the individual burden borne by Shurberg (which they exaggerate), forgetting the Supreme Court’s admonition that innocent parties may sometimes be asked to bear the burden of affirmative action programs. See Wygant, 476 U.S. at 280-81, 106 S.Ct. at 1850 (Opinion of Powell, J.) (”[a]s part of this Nation's dedication to eradicating racial discrimination, innocent persons may be called upon to bear some of the burden of the remedy"). An absolutist prohibition on any such transfer would call into question virtually all of the affirmative action programs at universities because in most cases some nonmi-nority applicant loses his opportunity to enter the college of his choice. Similarly, it places in doubt affirmative action programs in the workplace because often an unhired nonminority applicant may not have any other opportunity to ply his trade in the same community. These are serious burdens for individuals, but they have not been held to invalidate otherwise legitimate affirmative action programs. My colleagues’ approach suggests — erroneously in my view — that affirmative action is permissible only when nothing very important is at stake, when such a superabundance of opportunity exists that no one need go without.
. Judge Silberman suggests that I am unclear as to whether the distress sale policy is in fact a "remedial” program. See Silberman op. at 914 n. 13. The confusion, I would submit, stems from the ambiguous nature of the term "remedial.” The distress sale program is not "remedial” in the narrow sense in which that term is sometimes used: its purpose is not to compensate particular minority individuals for past injustices by providing them with increased economic opportunities in broadcasting. It is, however, “remedial” in a broader sense: it seeks to address (or remedy) a societal problem (the under-representation of minorities in the broadcast field, and the consequent lack of diverse programming) which has been caused by past racial discrimination. I therefore believe that the Supreme Court’s repeated references to the broad remedial powers of Congress bolster congressional authority to implement this program as a means of enhancing diversity. See supra, pp. 941-43.
Rehearing
ON PETITIONS FOR REHEARING
ORDER
Upon consideration of the petitions for rehearing of appellee and intervenor it is ORDERED, by the Court, that the petitions are denied.
I vote to deny rehearing by the panel and the suggestion for rehearing en banc for the reasons set forth below.
From existing decisional law it must be concluded that any racial or group preference is inherently suspect, must be subject to close and careful scrutiny and can only be upheld to justify an award to promote programming diversity if it is one of several factors that entered into the decision. J.A. Croson Co. v. City of Richmond, — U.S. -, 109 S.Ct. 706, 721, 102 L.Ed.2d 854 (O’Connor, J.), 109 S.Ct. at 735 (Scalia, J.) (1989) (citations to the slip opinion). In other words, racial or group preference violates equal protection if, as here, it is the only basis for a federal agency preferring one applicant over another. As Justice Powell stated in his opinion, University of California Regents v. Bakke, 438 U.S. 265, 98 S.Ct. 2733, 57 L.Ed.2d 750 (1978):
“[Pjreferring members of any one group for no reason other than race or ethnic origin is discrimination for its own sake. This the constitution forbids.”
Bakke at 307, 98 S.Ct. at 2757 (Powell, J.). Cf. Johnson v. Transportation Agency, 480 U.S. 616, 638, 107 S.Ct. 1442, 1455, 94 L.Ed.2d 615 (1987) (Title VII analysis).
The standards of the Federal Communications Commission’s distress sale policy here in question provide that certain minority groups shall have an absolute preference over all other citizens in qualifying for a broadcast license that is designated for hearing. The preferred minority groups are defined and restricted to those who are:
“black, Hispanic surnamed, American Eskimo, Aleut, American Indian and Asiatic American extraction,” 68 FCC2d at 781 n. 8 (1978).
Even all non-minority women are excluded. The preferred group in this case is: “Hispanic surnamed.” With all the intermarriages, having a Hispanic surname is no guarantee that a person is “Hispanic” or a minority to any substantial degree — though this opinion makes nothing of this point. In my opinion there is no possibility that an absolute group preference can be held to be constitutional under the equal protection standard implicit in the 5th Amendment.
With the case in its present posture nothing would be gained by rehearing. The Commission has been absolutely prohibited by Congress from making any change or even determining the facts to justify the validity of the program. In addition, the Commission has vacillated from one position to another like a teeter-totter and when it filed its opinion in this case was in one of its 2 to 1 reversal moods due to two unfilled Commission vacancies. These two Commissioners stated that the program is constitutional. However, the Commission’s earlier brief to the en banc court in Steele v. FCC, 770 F.2d 1192 (D.C.Cir.1985), vacated and rehearing en banc granted, Order of Oct. 31, 1985, remanded, Order of October 9, 1986 (FCC Brief at 15), stated that the Commission’s racial and gender preference policies, which would include the distress sale program, were unconstitutional. The Commission’s Steele Brief on Rehearing En Banc stated:
I. THE FCC’S CURRENT POLICY OF GRANTING RACE AND GENDER PREFERENCES CONFLICTS WITH CONSTITUTIONAL STANDARDS.
The racial and gender preference policies employed by the FCC in comparative licensing proceedings since 1978 are discriminatory classifications by government that are inherently suspect, presumptively invalid and subject to stringent scrutiny under the equal protection guarantee implicit in the due process clause of the Fifth Amendment. See Wygant v. Jackson Bd. of Educ. [476 U.S. 267, 273, 106 S.Ct. 1842, 1846], 90 L.Ed.2d 260, 268 (1986); Lehr v. Robertson, 463 U.S. 248, 265-66 [103 S.Ct. 2985, 2995-96, 77 L.Ed.2d 614] (1983).
Properly balanced programming diversity of viewpoint in mass media is an acceptable goal, but the Commission in its long history of awarding broadcast licenses has never thwarted that objective by uneonstitutionally discriminating against minorities. The objective of programming diversity whether considered as satisfying the 5th Amendment, or as authorized by the 14th Amendment, must meet some modicum of equal protection.
The dissent states at n. 3 that if this case was reheard "on the merits” by the court en banc and the court was equally divided the FCC’s decision would be upheld. I fail to understand the significance of this speculation. As the court is presently constituted, en banc consideration of this case would not ordinarily result in an equally divided court. The en banc court would include the senior circuit judge who participated in the original panel, which, based on positions presently expressed, would result in a 6-5 vote affirming the reasoning of the majority decision of the panel. See Boeing Company v. Shipman, 411 F.2d 365, 367 (5th Cir.1969); Luna v. Beto, 395 F.2d 35, 37 (5th Cir.1968); Allen v. Johnson, 391 F.2d 527 (5th Cir.1968); cf. Tavoulareas v. Piro, 817 F.2d 762 (D.C.Cir.1987) (En Banc) (two Senior Circuit Judges participating in rehearing en banc due to their participation in the original three judge panel.). Thus, only delay would be the most likely result from granting rehearing en banc.
Dennis R. Patrick, as Chairman of the Federal Communications Commission, in his dissenting opinion, has set forth the material facts and the law in an admirable opinion. The dissent would denigrate the soundness of the Chairman’s opinion because he has subsequently resigned. The soundness of a legal decision is not diminished by the resignation or death of an official. Chief Justice Marshall’s opinions and those of all prior judges still survive as precedents. The evaluation of the legal reasoning in Chairman Patrick’s dissent is entitled to be evaluated on the basis of its legal merits to the same extent as the dissent in this case. Because Chairman Patrick’s excellent opinion succinctly covers the entire background and the law applicable to each phase of this case, it de
APPENDIX
DISSENTING OPINION OF CHAIRMAN PATRICK OF THE FEDERAL COMMUNICATIONS COMMISSION IN SHURBERG.
“The Commission’s minority preference policies have a tortured past. The Commission initially took the position that minority preferences should be granted only after the minority applicant clearly demonstrated that program and viewpoint diversity would be fostered through minority ownership. After being directed by the D.C. Circuit to presume a nexus between minority ownership and program diversity,
In Shurberg, each of the three separate opinions treats West Michigan differently. Judge Silberman questions West Michigan ’s initial conclusion that there is a compelling government interest in increasing diversity of programming and goes on to conclude that it may, in any event, be undermined by the Supreme Court’s recent
Recent Supreme Court precedents collectively make clear that racial and gender classifications are inherently suspect and will be subject to close and careful scrutiny.
The first stage of equal protection analysis under strict scrutiny requires a determination as to whether there is a compelling government objective. The Supreme Court has only identified two compelling interests for race-based policies. First, such minority preference policies may be implemented to remedy past discrimination. Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 475 [100 S.Ct. at 2773].
From this second justification, the D.C. Circuit in West Michigan extrapolated to find “program diversity” in broadcasting a compelling interest. This premise, set out in West Michigan, relies on Justice Powell’s opinion in Bakke that a diverse educational environment is a compelling goal that may be constitutionally promoted by certain admissions policies which recognize race as one of several factors. As racial diversity is only one aspect of a truly diverse student body, Justice Powell believed that a university could use race as one factor in a multi-factor admissions decision.
Similarly, if one assume program diversity to be a compelling goal, race is but one factor which may bear on diversity of view
Citing Fullilove, my fellow Commissioners see no reason why the court should not extend its findings in the remedial context to the diversity arena. I submit that one does not necessarily lead to the other. It is clear after the Supreme Court’s decision in Croson that race-based measures are subject to the highest degree of scrutiny. Where evidence of past discrimination exists, the Court may well tolerate race-based remedial measures. But where the most nebulous goal of diversity is at issue, the most that even Justice Powell would permit is the consideration of race as one of several factors. There is no basis to think the Court would allow more.
Ensuring that minority perspectives can be aired in a diverse broadcast marketplace is an important policy goal which I support. But our station licensing and transfer policies must, above all else, guarantee equal protection of the laws to all Americans. As such, our race-conscious policies must be subjected to the most rigorous review to insure fidelity to this principle.
. The dissent cites Justice Scalia’s statement in his concurring opinion in City of Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co., — U.S. -, 109 S.Ct. 706, 102 L.Ed.2d 854 (1989) which notes that Congress, pursuant to Section 5 of the 14th Amendment, possess augmented legislative powers “concerning matters of race.” Statement of dissent denying rehearing en banc at 958-959 Shurberg Broadcasting of Hartford, Inc. v. Federal Communications Commission, No. 84-1600 (quoting City of Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co., supra, Scalia, J., 109 S.Ct. at 736). This citation implies that Congress’ by virtue of Section 5 of the 14th Amendment has augmented legislative powers which extend beyond the power to enact race conscious legislation to remedy prior group discrimination, and extends to authorize legislation designed to promote diversity. In this respect the dissent is troubling for the far reaching consequences it may sow. Clearly, the Croson decision does not warrant such an assumption. In Croson, the Court considered Richmond’s affirmative action program which was designed to remedy prior racial discrimination in the city. Croson 109 S.Ct. at 713; 109 S.Ct. at 735 (Scalia, J.). Justice Scalia’s reference to the Congress’ “enhanced powers" under Section 5 of the 14th Amendment must be interpreted as addressing legislation designed to remedy prior discrimination. Similarly, Chief Justice Burger's opinion in Fullilove v. Klutznick, 448 U.S. 448, 100 S.Ct. 2758, 65 L.Ed.2d 902 (1980), outlined Congress’ powers under the 14th Amendment in the context of legislation designed to remedy prior racial discrimination:
Here we deal, as we noted earlier, not with the limited remedial powers of a federal court, for example, but with the broad remedial powers of Congress. It is fundamental that in no organ of government, state or federal, does there repose a more comprehensive remedial power than in Congress, expressly charged by the Constitution with the competence and authority to enforce equal protection guarantees.
Fullilove at 483, 100 S.Ct. at 2777 (Burger, C.J.) (emphasis added). The dissent seeks, without discussion or citations to authority, to rely on Section 5 of the 14th Amendment as a positive grant of legislative power to Congress to enact race conscious programs designed to promote diversity absent any evidence of prior racial discrimination.
The implied assertion of the dissent that a legislative objective other than the remedying of past discrimination is entitled to heightened deference pursuant to Section 5 of the 14th Amendment is alarming because it has no logical stopping point. Judge Silberman has also expressed doubts as to whether Congress is entitled to enhanced deference under the 14th Amendment outside the remedial context. Sil-berman at 923. Moreover, a plurality of the Supreme Court stated that race conscious programs should be "strictly reserved for remedial settings.” Croson 109 S.Ct. at 721 (O’Connor, J.); at 736 (Scalia, J.); See Silberman at 920. To accord Congress heightened deference under the 14th Amendment outside remedial settings would grant the Legislative Branch a broad li
. The fact that Chairman Patrick favored rehearing en banc in this case and Winter Park was not stated because it is not relevant here. He supported rehearing en banc for Shurberg only if Winter Park was included. However, Winter Park is distinguishable on two material grounds. It involved (1) a comparative hearing and (2) the minority preference was only a plus factor. In Shurberg minority preference is an absolute preference. This case is not to be contrasted with a case which involved race as only one factor in a comparative licensing procedure.
. TV 9, Inc. v. FCC, 495 F.2d 939 [929], (D.C.Cir.1973), cert. denied, 419 U.S. 986 [95 S.Ct. 245, 42 L.Ed.2d 194] (1974).
. See Making Further Continuing Appropriations for Fiscal Year 1988 and for Other Purposes, Pub.L. No. 100-202 (signed Dec. 22, 1987). The appropriations legislation prohibits the Commission from using funds "to repeal, to retroactively apply changes in, or to continue a reexamination of’ the Commission’s policies premised on racial, ethnic or gender classification, except to: (1) close its proceeding investigating the preference policies; (2) reinstate prior policy; and (3) lift any suspension imposed on implementing the policies pending its investigation.
. See e.g., City of Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co., 57 U.S.L.W. 4132 [— U.S. -, 109 S.Ct. 706, 102 L.Ed.2d 854] (U.S. Jan. 23, 1989); Wygant v. Jackson Board of Education, [476 U.S. 267, 106 S.Ct. 1842] 90 L.Ed.2d 260 (1986); Fullilove v. Klutznik, 448 U.S. 448 [100 S.Ct. 2758, 65 L.Ed.2d 902] (1980); Regents of the University of California v. Bakke, 438 U.S. 265 [98 S.Ct. 2733, 57 L.Ed.2d 750] (1978). See also Mississippi University for Women v. Hogan, 458 U.S. 718 [102 S.Ct. 3331, 73 L.Ed.2d 1090] (1982).
. The Commission has never claimed that its preference policies are intended to remedy prior discrimination against minorities or to provide remedial benefits. It could be argued that Congress has separately adopted our policies as its own, with the justification that its policies are remedial. But Congress did not justify its funding decisions remedial. As my fellow Commissioners agree, Congress relied solely on a diversity rationale. FCC Petition or Rehearing at n. 1.
. It is unclear after Croson whether Justice Powell’s diversity rationale would be endorsed by the present Court. A plurality of the Court in that case quite clearly stated that classifications based on race should be "strictly reserved for remedial settings.” Croson, 57 U.S.L.W. at 4139 [— U.S. at -, 109 S.Ct. at 721], see also id. at 4145 [-, 109 S.Ct. at 735] (Scalia, J., concurring). And Justice O’Connor, who had indicated some sympathy for Justice Powell’s diversity rationale, Wygant, 476 U.S. at 286 [106 S.Ct. at 1852] (O’Connor, J., concurring), appears to have rejected that rationale in Croson. Justice Stevens interpreted Justice O’Connor's opinion as such a rejection, Croson, 57 U.S.L.W. at 4144 n. 1 [— U.S. at - n. 1, 109 S.Ct. at 730 n. 1] (Stevens, J., concurring in part), as has Judge Silberman, Shurberg, Silberman opin. at 919-921. While Judge Wald agrees as to the substance of Justice Stevens’ interpretation of the O’Connor opinion, Shurberg, Wald opin. at 942 n. 20 (dissenting), she herself would read that same opinion differently. With all due respect to Judge Wald, I must defer to the interpretation of Croson rendered by a member of the Supreme Court. Thus, in light of the Court’s decision in Croson, whether the academic diversity rationale remains as a compelling government interest for race-based policies is an open question. Certainly then, extensions of that rationale cannot be supported.
.The plan before the Bakke court, however, employed a racial set-aside, which did not account for other diversity factors. As Justice Powell wrote in Bakke, “preferring members of any one group for no reason other than race or ethic origin is discrimination for its own sake. This the Constitution forbids.” Bakke, 438 U.S. at 307 [98 S.Ct. at 2757]. The Court thus struck that plan down as unconstitutional.
. As I have previously noted, however, the Commission has been prohibited from determining whether race is a factor in viewpoint diversity, that is, whether there is a nexus between minority ownership and programming.
Dissenting Opinion
joined by ROBINSON, MIKVA, EDWARDS and RUTH B. GINSBURG, Circuit Judges, dissenting from denial of rehearing en banc:
My dissent from the panel’s disposition of this case sets forth my reasons for concluding that the distress sale policy is a constitutional exercise of congressional power. For several reasons, I regard this case as sufficiently important to warrant en banc reconsideration.
First, the continued use of the distress sale policy has been mandated by an Act of Congress. The panel opinions in this case rely heavily on the Supreme Court’s decisions in Wygant v. Jackson Board of Education, 476 U.S. 267, 106 S.Ct. 1842, 90 L.Ed.2d 260 (1986) and City of Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co., — U.S. -, 109 S.Ct. 706, 102 L.Ed.2d 854 (1989), both of which involved affirmative plans initiated by local authorities. Of the six Justices who comprised the Croson majority, however, four
Second, the agency itself, despite its pri- or misgivings, has now indicated clearly that it supports the distress sale policy — a fact which was not free from doubt at the time of the panel’s decision.
Finally, the panel’s disposition of this case creates considerable doubt as to whether the pursuit of diversity remains a viable justification for affirmative action programs in any setting. This aspect of the panel opinions has constitutional ramifications stretching well beyond the broadcasting context; clearly it calls into question the constitutionality of affirmative action programs in student admissions at public universities.
For the foregoing reasons, I dissent from the denial of rehearing en banc. The denial of review, by an equally divided court,
. Judge MacKinnon attaches great significance to the fact that the agency’s decision to seek rehearing was made by a 2-1 vote. My colleague provides lengthy excerpts from FCC Chairman Dennis Patrick’s dissent from the Commission’s position to petition for en banc review. Since Chairman Patrick was the lone dissenter, and since he has resigned from his post on the Commission, effective upon the appointment of his successor, his views are hardly the best indicator of the agency’s current position.
Moreover, Chairman Patrick’s opposition to rehearing of this case was hardly unequivocal. The Chairman stated:
In light of the importance and complexity of these issues, particularly given recent Congressional actions and the varying opinions in Shurberg and [ Winter Park Communications, Inc. v. FCC, 873 F.2d 347 (D.C.Cir.1989) ], I would petition the D.C. Circuit to hear Shur-berg en banc and support a petition for rehearing on Winter Park. Both cases could be considered together and the court could give us definitive guidance. But I cannot support my fellow Commissioners' approach of requesting only partial enlightenment in this area.
Dissenting Statement of Chairman Dennis R. Patrick at 3.
Nor do the agency’s recent doubts concerning the distress sale policy impugn the Commission's current support. After all, the FCC's prior enforcement of the fairness doctrine did not invalidate its recent decision that the doctrine should be repealed. See Syracuse Peace Council v. FCC, 867 F.2d 654 (D.C.Cir.1989). The Commission’s prior doubts simply reflect the fact that this is a complex and difficult area of the law — hardly an argument against en banc review.
. The original panel produced three different views on this issue. Judge Silberman expressed doubt as to whether the diversity rationale for racial preferences remains viable in light of Croson, even in the context of higher education. See Silberman op. at 919-20. Judge Mac-Kinnon declined to reach the question. See MacKinnon op. at 930 n. 11. I expressed the view that the pursuit of diversity is a sufficiently important interest to justify the use of racial preferences. See Wald op. at 941-42. Certainly the panel opinions do not foreclose all diversity-based plans in other contexts, but they are likely to spawn considerable uncertainty and confu
Moreover, all nine Justices in Regents of the University of California v. Bakke, 438 U.S. 265, 98 S.Ct. 2733, 57 L.Ed.2d 750 (1978), concluded that Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. § 2000d, imposes restrictions at least as severe as those established by the Constitution. See Bakke, 438 U.S. at 286-87, 98 S.Ct. at 2746-47 (Opinion of Powell, J.); id. at 328-40, 98 S.Ct. at 2767-73 (Opinion of Brennan, White, Marshall, and Blackmun, JJ.); id. at 416, 98 S.Ct. at 2812 (Opinion of Stevens, J.). If public university admissions programs which take account of race are constitutionally proscribed, that proscription would also apply to private universities receiving federal funds.
. I would note that when an en banc court is equally divided on the merits, the decision of the agency is affirmed. See Handbook of Practice and Internal Procedures, United States Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit at 68 (1987).
Rehearing
ON SUGGESTIONS FOR REHEARING EN BANC
ORDER
The suggestions for rehearing en banc of appellee and intervenor have been circulated to the full court. The taking of a vote was requested. Thereafter, a majority of the judges of the Court in regular active service did not vote in favor of either suggestion. Upon consideration of the foregoing it is
ORDERED, by the Court en banc, that the suggestions are denied.
Chief Judge WALD and Circuit Judges ROBINSON, MIKVA, EDWARDS and RUTH B. GINSBURG would grant the suggestions.
A statement of Chief Judge WALD, joined by Circuit Judges ROBINSON, MIKVA, EDWARDS and RUTH B. GINSBURG, is attached.
Former Circuit Judge STARR did not participate in this matter while a member of the Court.