51 Cal. 243 | Cal. | 1876
Lead Opinion
“Taxation shall be equal and uniform throughout the State. All property in this State shall be taxed in proportion to its value, to be ascertained as directed by law; but assessors and collectors of town, county and State taxes shall be elected by the qualified electors of the district, county or town in which the property taxed for State, county or town purposes is situated.” (Constitution of California, Article IX, section 13.)
. There is no provision in the Political Code which requires, in terms, that debts secured by mortgage shall be taxed. That Code requires that all property shall be taxed, and section seventeen declares: “The words ‘personal property ’ include money, goods, chattels, evidence of debt, and ‘ tilings in action.’”
Unless' the provision of the Constitution above quoted restrains or limits the power of the Legislature, so as to prohibit the taxation of “evidences of debt and things in action,” it is the duty of the assessors to assess not only
And this, 1st, because it is the established law that all property must be taxed, and the Legislature has no power to exempt any property; and 2d, because the Legislature has declared that all property shall be taxed, and attempted to include in the definition of property all dioses in action.
But to declare that it is the duty of the assessor to assess all “things in action,” is to give a construction to the Constitution which must lead to the grossest absurdities. The Constitution, in its application to the various departments of the Government, and to individual rights, must receive such a construction as to give it a practical operation. There would be a contradiction in the single section of the Constitution, if it were construed as requiring that all property should be taxed equally and uniformly with reference to its value, and that the word property includes those things practically incapable of an appraisement bearing any definite relation or proportion to other things or property.
That causes of action are dependent on too many contingencies to be capable of appraisement which shall accord with any rule of equality or uniformity of value, is too plain for argument.
Tet the Constitution requires that all property shall be assessed on the ad valorem principle by local assessors. All property which is visible and tangible is capable of such assessment; dioses in action are not. The word “property” has been used in our language in several senses; but in the case in hand we cannot, be limited to the meaning given it by the Code, but may also—and such is our duty— look for its meaning in the Constitution. The Constitution provides that no property, as property, shall be taxed except such as is capable of a valuation by the assessors, which shall be ratably equal and uniform with that affixed to all other property.
In Houghton v. Austin (47 Cal. 661), it was held that taxation must be thus equal and uniform; and in People v. San
The thirteenth section of Article XI of the Constitution requires that each article of property, capable of valuation, shall be fixed or estimated, and the owner thereof made to pay a sum, which shall bear the same proportion to the whole amount levied as does the value of the particular property to the aggregate value of all the property in the State or tax district.
Under our Constitution, therefore, the subject of taxation is the sum of all the values.
Independent of other constitutional restrictions the State might take such portions of the wealth within its borders— the burden being distributed with uniformity—as the legislative department might deem necessary for the support or defense of the Government. In this respect there would be no limitation, save that resulting from moral considerations, addressing themselves to the consciences of individual legislators. Supposing — what would thus be possible in theory—that the necessities of Government required a tax of one hundred per cent, on all values; or, what would be the result of such a tax, an appropriation of all the property in the State, it is plain that the State would receive no benefit from evidences of debt due by some of her citizens to others, and payable out of the tangible property which the State had already taken.
It is property in possession or enjoyment, and not merely in right, which must ultimately pay every tax.
The Legislature may declare that a cause of action shall be taxed, but a cause of action cannot pay the tax; and this because it has, and can have, no value independent of the tangible wealth out of which it may be satisfied.
In a certain sense a promissory note or any credit is property. Whether “ solvent,” as the term is ordinarily employed, or not, it may be assigned for value; it would be difficult, however, to explain why a note discounted at twenty per cent, would be less appropriately called “ property ” than one sold at par. In any case, a credit has no
The sovereign power of the people, in employing the prerogative of taxation, regards not the claims of individuals on individuals, but deals with the aggregate wealth of all; that which is supposed to be unlimited is here limited by an inexorable law which parliaments cannot set aside, for it is only to the actual wealth that governments can resort, and, that exhausted, they have no other property resource. This is as certain as that a paper promise to pay money is not money.
It may not be possible in every case to show that the debtor has paid the tax assessed to his creditor. But it admits of mathematical demonstration—if the other property in the State has been assessed at its value—that the money which shall ultimately satisfy the debt (if it is ever satisfied) has paid its tax. If it were practicable to assess all the property in the State at the same moment of time, it would be clear to every mind that an assessment of a credit was an attempt to transfer to it a value elsewhere assessed. It may happen, as the assessor goes his round, that the same piece of tangible personal property is in fact twice taxed; but in every such case the presumption is that he first found in possession has parted with it for its value; that when the second person is assessed, the first has received other property of'like value to that twice assessed; so that the uniformity required by the Constitution is maintained in effect. But if a debtor is found to be the owner of one thousand dollars, and is assessed for that sum, and his creditor is found to be the owner of his note for one thousand dollars, and is assessed for a like sum; and if, the day after the visit of the assessor to the creditor the debtor shall pay his note, it is clear that the same value has been twice
In People v. Eddy (43 Cal. 336), this Court said: “The word 1 property ’ is used in that section of the Constitution in its ordinary and popular sense, and this is the general rule in the interpretation of constitutions and statutes, unless the context shows that the words are used in a technical or some arbitrary sense.” With this general proposition I fully agree, but I am not prepared to admit that, in its vulgar sense, the word 11 property ” includes- all choses in action. And I feel compelled to dissent from the statement which follows, in the same opinion: “ There is no good reason to believe that the word was used in that section (section thirteen, Article XI), in a sense materially differing from that which it has in other sections of that instrument.” A single illustration will show that the foregoing is not literally correct. It has never been doubted in these arguments that gold and silver money is property which may be taxed. Such coins are more than promises to pay; they are composed of metals recognized - as standards of value throughout the commercial world, and everywhere of purchasing capacity. But it has been repeatedly held that the clause of the Constitution (Article I, section eight): “Nor shall private properly be taken for public use without just compensation,” prohibits the taking of money. The reason is apparent. The compensation spoken of is money, and it would lead to an absurdity to say that money should be taken for the public, only in case an equal sum of money should be paid to the citizen when the money was taken. Such is the uncertainty of human language, that it is absolutely necessary to consider the context in order to determine the sense in which a particular word is employed, if it can ever be employed in more than one.
The facts of the present case do not present any question as to the power of the Legislature to require the payment
The views above expressed remove the objection heretofore resorted to, that the creditor cannot complain if the debtor shall pay a double tax. The creditor can always complain, because the credit should not be taxed at all, inasmuch as it has no independent value, and, therefore, cannot be taxed in proportion to such value (as part of the aggregate of values) in the manner required by the Constitution.
And in the foregoing an effort has been made to abstain from any reference to the moral effects of a species of legislation which ordinarily transfers the burden of taxation from the lender to the borrower, and encourages misrepresentation and perjury by permitting the collection of a tax to depend upon the oath of the creditor based on his opinion of the solvency of his debtors. The case should be decided by reference to the power of the Legislature under the Constitution.
I am of the opinion that “credits” are not “property” subject to taxation within the meaning of the section of the Constitution above quoted.
Judgment reversed and cause remanded. Remittitur forthwith.
Concurrence Opinion
concurring:
The question in hand is whether “credits” are “property” in the sense in which the latter word is employed in the thirteenth section of the eleventh article of the Constitution, which requires all “property” to be taxed in proportion to its value.
It is not doubted, of course, that even though credits be not property in the sense referred to, and consequently, not to be taxed as property, the Legislature may, nevertheless, in its discretion, impose a tax upon such credits, as for instance, it may require stamps of graduated denomination to be affixed to each promissory note or evidence of indebtedness executed, which form of tax, when put in operation, would probably enable everybody (certainly all borrowers)
Returning, ■ then, to the question whether credits must be considered to be “property” in the sense adverted to, it will be remembered that the affirmative was maintained here in People v. McCreery (34 Cal. 432), and upon the authority of that case was assumed in People v. Eddy (43 Cal. 331). The question, however, involving as it does the correct construction of the text of the Constitution itself, in respect to a matter of such great and constantly recurring importance as the working of the general revenue system of the State, is not, in my opinion, to be determined by reference to mere precedents, or to decisions already made.
Considerations, upon which the doctrine of stare decisis is supposed to be founded, certainly do not attach to a controversy of this character. A re-examination of the general question, wholly unembarrassed by what our predecessors or we ourselves may have said, if seen to have been ill-founded in law, does not involve either the possible disturbance of vested rights, or the overthrow of rules of property supposed to have become fixed and settled.
I am of opinion that credits are not property, in the sense in which the word “property” is used in the thirteenth section of the eleventh article of the Constitution. That credits are correctly designated as “property,” in a general sense, no one of course will deny; and that they fall within the true meaning of that word, as employed in other portions of the Constitution, is readily conceded.
But, as observed by Vattel, “it does not follow either logically or grammatically that because a word occurs in one section with a definite sense, that therefore the same sense is to be adopted in every other section in which it occurs.” (Book 2, Ch. 17, Sec. 285.)
It certainly requires neither discussion nor authority to show that in searching for the true sense in which a word has been used in a particular instance, it is proper—in fact, often indispensable—to consider as well the subject-matter which it concerns, as the immediate connection in which it
The language found in the thirteenth section of the eleventh article of the Constitution, referred to, is as follows: “Taxation shall be equal and uniform throughout the State. All property in this State shall be taxed in proportion to its value,” etc.
This provision of the Constitution established the cardinal rule that property taxation in this State should always be imposed upon an ad valorem, as contradistinguished from a specific basis, and may be paraphrased thus: ‘ ‘All the actual wealth within this State shall be equally burdened with the support of the Government.” That “property,” as here employed in the Constitution, and “actual wealth,” as used in the paraphrase, are synonymous, and that each of them alike excludes mere credits, is believed to be demonstrable. In the nature of things, both the scale of public expenditure indulged and the consequent degree of taxation necessary for its supply have reference to the actual aggregate wealth for the political community to Avhich government looks for support. These habitually vary as the State is popularly said to be comparatively rich or comparatively poor.
The Legislature, in making up the budget, must necessarily therefore look to the aggregate amount of actual wealth in the hands of the people and borne upon the tax-rolls. This constitutes the capacity to pay, which it is always indispensable for the statesman to consider. And in considering it, how, it may be asked, can it be supposed that the aggregate wealth of the people—their actual capacity to pay taxes—is at all made up of credits—the mere indebtedness OAving by individual members of the body politic to others of its members ?
An answer would perhaps most readily be found in supposing, were such a thing possible, that the entire tax-rolls exhibited nothing but such indebtedness. Taxation attempted under such circumstances would of course be wholly fanciful, as bavin#? no actual basis for its exercise.
The taxation thus imposed nominally upon “credits’’ having resulted in the double taxation of the money, the additional tax must, of course, be paid by some one. And here all human experience, as well as the settled theories of finance, concur that it is not the lender who pays—-but the borrower. The borrower is the consumer. The interest which he pays to the lender is the prime cost of the delay for which he has contracted. If the government, by the imposition of additional taxes, increase the cost, the borrower, being the consumer, must pay it. The truth of this
I, therefore, concur that the judgment of the court below be reversed.
Concurrence Opinion
concurring:
I concur in the opinion of Mr. Justice McKinstry; and while it is not to be denied that the proposition that solvent debts are not “property” for the purposes of taxation within the intent of Article XI, section thirteen of the Constitution, it is in conflict with several prior decisions of this Court. I am satisfied, upon more mature deliberation and in the light of the later and more eXhaustive arguments of the questions, that the former rulings on this point cannot be supported. The Constitution being the fundamental law, it is of the utmost consequence to the people that its provisions should be properly construed. This is peculiarly true of those provisions relating to the power of taxation—a power more subject to abuse than any other, and which directly affects the interest of every citizen. Whatever weight may be due to the rule of stare decisis, as applied to other subjects, it ought not, in my opinion, to prevent a return to a proper construction of those provisions of the Constitution which affect the vital question of taxation. No great property rights have grown up under the former construction, which can be injuriously affected by the change in the rule; and*254 I discover no sufficient reason for persisting in a construction, the only effect of which, in a large majority of cases, is, to inflict upon the borrowers of money an unjust and oppressive system of double taxation. That this is the necessary result of a tax on debts secured by mortgage for money loaned, is, in my opinion, too plain to admit of debate. In the case of the Savings and Loan Society v. Austin (46 Cal. 415), I have stated at length my reasons for that opinion, and it is unnecessary to repeat them here. I still adhere to that opinion; and in addition to the reasons stated by Mr. Justice McKlnstry why the tax involved in the present case should be set aside, I think that the facts disclosed by this record present a clear case of double taxation of the same subject-matter; and the tax having been paid by the mortgagors, cannot again be collected from the mortgagee.
But while holding that solvent debts are not “property” in the sense of Article XI, Sec. 13, of the Constitution, and therefore are not required to be taxed on the ad valorem principle, it does not follow that the Legislature is for that reason powerless to tax them in some other form. It exercises unquestioned the right to tax avocations, not because an avocation is property, but because the power and mode of taxation are unlimited, except in so far as they are restricted by the Constitution; and Article XI, Sec. 13, prescribes the method only in respect to such subjects of taxation as are “property” in the' sense of that clause. Solvent debts not being “property” in that sense, cannot be taxed as such under that provision, as was attempted to be done in the present case. But it might be competent for the Legislature to require a stamp tax on a mortgage or a promissory note, for the same reason that it may tax the avocation of an auctioneer. In that event it would be a tax on the transaction of making the note or mortgage, and not a tax on the debt as property.
Mr. Justice Bhodes dissented.