12 Tex. 462 | Tex. | 1854
To reverse the, judgment of conviction it is urged that the Court erroneously excluded evidence proposed1 by the accused ; and also that there is error in the charge of the Court.
The attorney for the State had asked a witness how the accused was “ equipped ” as he rode into Jefferson with the witness on the morning of the day of the killing. To which the witness answered that “ he had pistols tied to his saddle,” and the defence thereupon proposed to prove by the witness that the accused “ uttered no hostile expressions about the deceased and spoke of no difficulty with any onewhich, upon objection, the Court excluded ; and this is assigned as error.
The attorney for the State had not questioned the witness as to any statements or conversations of the accused at the time. And yet it is insisted that the accused had the right to prove that he did not use threatening language, or give expression to any hostile intentions toward the deceased. The proposition was to prove what the accused did not say, when there had been no question asked as to what he did say. It is scarcely necessary to say that a party could not thus make evidence for himself; that the testimony proposed was irrelevant ; did not conduce to prove any fact pertinent to the issue, was no part of the res gestae; nor of a conversation drawn out by the examination on the part of the State ; and was very clearly inadmissible.
By a “ threatened attack ” it is evident the Court meant the previous threats of the deceased. The Judge could have meant; and the jury could have understood him to mean nothing else; for there was no pretence of attack or threatened attack by deceased at the time of the killing. Divested of the peculiar phraseology which obscures its meaning—that is, the expressions “ not being moved by a wicked and malicious intent,” “ well grounded apprehension,” and “ threatened attack ;” and viewed in reference to the fact of the case—the legal proposition which the charge announces is, that previous threats, of themselves, and unconnected with any manifestation at ‘ the time of the killing of an intention to carry them into immediate execution, will extenuate the crime and penalty of a willful, premeditated and deliberate homicide, ■committed in cold blood, by one laying in wait purposely to take the life of his adversary; if the motive which actuated the slayer was the preservation of his own life from future, ■and of course, contingent danger, apprehended by violence from the deceased. Or, in other words, that bare, naked threats unconnected with acts, may extenuate and reduce the crime of murder, committed by a “ premeditated and deliberate tilling,” which the statute defines to be murder in the first degree, to murder in the second degree.
It could not have been intended to invoke any principle of the law upon the subject of provocation, as having any, the remotest application to the case before the Court; or to rest the doctrine asserted as to the effect of previous threats upon this ground. For if there had been what the law regards as provocation sufficient to extenuate the crime, it could not have been murder of either degree; but would be manslaughter only.
The right of self-defence rests upon the law of necessity. It is the natural and inalienable right of every human being; and it is to be held sacred and inviolable by any law of human or civil institution. It does not depend upon any law of society. It is derived from a higher source ; is coevil with man’s natural being ; and hence it is with truth and reason said, that self-preservation is the first law of nature. “ Self- “ defence, therefore, (says Blackstone) as it is justly called the “ primary law of nature, so it is not, neither can it be in fact, “ taken away by the law of society.” (3 Bl. 4.) It may be rightfully exercised by every human being, whether beneath - a despot’s rule, or on freedom’s soil; whether he exists in a heathen land, or breathes beneath a Christian sun. But still, it is a law of necessity; and while, in its just and proper exercise it places the subject of it above and beyond the influence of the civil or municipal law; renders him irresponsible for his acts done by its permission, and not amenable to the civil authority; yet it has its limit, as well defined as is the limit of any right which a man may exercise in subordination to the laws of society ; and that limit is where the necessity which gave the right ceases. The necessity and the right are from their nature co-extensive and concurrent. Where the
It is the necessary consequence of the right of self-defence, and therefore it is the universally received principle and maxim of the law, that “ a man may repel force by force in the
There is and can be no pretence that the facts of the present case bring it within any of these rules, which ascertain and mark the limit of the lawful exercise of the right of self-defence. There is no dispute about the facts. The accused was not the party attacked. He was the assailant; not the deceased. There is no pretence of an attack or threatened attack from the latter, present and impending over the accused at the time of the commission of the homicide. The accused was the sole aggressor, on that occasion. There was at the time no danger, and could have been no apprehension of present danger from the deceased; and of course, there was and could be no present necessity, or well grounded belief of the existence of a present necessity of taking his life by the accused for the preservation of his own life. The accused did not act on the defensive. Instead of endeavoring to avoid the necessity, he sought the occasion. Being apprised of the threats of the deceased, he went about compassing his destruction. He prepared for the occasion ; unobserved watched, or was apprised of the movements of the deceased—was under no necessity of encountering and did not encounter him in open combat, or on equal terms, if even that, where the occasion was sought by him, would have been a defence—but watched his opportunity, and when it was evident the deceased, if he had sought a rencounter, had given it over, at least for the time, he pursued, and unobserved by the deceased, took his position by the way side, where still unobserved, he waited his approach, and as the deceased was passing shot him from under cover without giving him timely notice to stand in defence of his life, or to make good his retreat; and only sufficient to embitter the last moment of his life by the consciousness that he died by the hand of his enemy.' We abstain from comment. It is unnecessary..
FTor could the Court have intended to rest the doctrine maintained, as to the effect of previous threats, on the ground that they supported this defence. For then they would have had the effect, not merely to extenuate from the first to the second degree of murder; but they would have constituted a complete justification or excuse of the homicide; and of course it could not have been murder of any degree, or manslaughter; but would be justifiable or excusable homicide.
The error of the Court evidently arose from confounding previous threats with a “ threatened attack,” or menacing, present danger; or, as the terms import, the manifestation by acts of a present intention of immediate attacking; and also from confounding malice in a legal sense, with malice in its popular signification ; in which it is used to denote an evil or malevolent motive and disposition of the mind ; and from not bearing in mind that every intentional killing of any human being, by a voluntary free agent of sound memory and discretion, unless justified by command of the law; excused by its permission, as in the case of self-defence; or extenuated by some sufficient legal provocation or by being the involuntary consequence of some act not strictly lawful; is, in a legal sense, malicious; and no inquiry can be instituted into the actual motive and disposition of mind which prompted the act, except by proof of the facts which make out the justification, legal excuse, or extenuation. For all homicide is presumed to be malicious, and of course amounting to murder,
If the idea, which the charge of the Court evidently conveys, that the real motive and disposition of mind which prompted the commission of the deed gives character to the crime and determines its degree, were the law, then there could be no
Every intentional killing is not necessarily murder. For it may be from a principle of inevitable necessity, and then it would be self-defence: it may be done in the transport of passion and heat of blood upon a sudden and sufficient legal provocation ; and then it will be manslaughter only: or it may
There can be no doubt, therefore, that the Court did err in the charge we have considered. But there is as little doubt that it was an error in favor of the appellant; one which operated in his favor; and which, under the evidence in the case, could not possibly have operated to his prejudice. And upon no principle can it be maintained that for such an error this Court would be warranted in reversing the judgment.
The cases cited by counsel for appellant (decided in Georgia and Tennessee) have not been adverted to, for the reason that they were not deemed applicable to the questions arising in this case. In Howell v. The State, (5 Geo. R. 48,) which was an indictment for an assault with intent to murder, the question was as to the admissibility in evidence of the threats of the party assaulted; and they were held admissible in evidence. In the present case they were admitted without objection ; and of course there was and could be no question to be determined upon this appeal, as to their admissibility. In Monroe v. The State, (Ib. 85,) which was an indictment for murder, the same point was raised and it was held _ that “ Threats accompanied with occasional acts of personal vio- “ lence, are admissible to justify the reasonableness of the defendant’s fears, provided a knowledge of the threats is brought “ home to him.” But there is no opinion advanced in the case which ascribes to mere threats unaccompanied with acts any such effect as is claimed for them in the present case. The other is the case of Grainger v. The State, (5 Yerger, 459,) which has been the subject of much comment, and doubtless, some misapprehension as to what it was intended to decide;
The present is deemed a fit occasion to remark that it is matter of surprise, that the Legislature should have thought proper to limit the security which may be had in a recognizance to bind over to keep the peace, before a Justice, to the sum of two thousand dollars ; to fix such a limit to the security which a man may demand, (without resorting to a higher tribunal, often impracticable,) against a threatened injury to his person or property. (Dig. Art. 1701.) It could scarcely have been intended to deny a man, whose personal safety is endangered by the wanton violence of another, the right to demand that that other should be restrained of his liberty and the ability to endanger his life and the peace of society, until he will give security in such a sumas will be amply sufficient to ensure that protection, which it is the duty of government and the intention of the law to afford. The law should extend
It is supposed that the object of fixing a limit to the amount of security in recognizance, which a Justice of the Peace may require, was to guard against an arbitrary abuse of power in those inferior magistrates. But when it is considered how very little danger is really to be apprehended from that source, compared with the danger that they will not act sufficiently energetically; and that in case of abuse, the writ of habeas corpus will afford ready relief, it will be apparent that the danger of an excessive exercise of power is rather imaginary than real. It is to be hoped that this feature, which now mars the code, will be effaced from its pages.
There is in the record no erroneous ruling adversely to the
Judgment affirmed.