537 U.S. 968 | SCOTUS | 2002
Dissenting Opinion
dissenting.
Petitioner has filed an application for an original writ of habeas corpus asking us to hold that his execution would be unconstitutional because he was under the age of 18 when he committed his offense. A bare majority of the Court rejected that submission 13 years ago. Stanford v. Kentucky, 492 U. S. 361 (1989). There are no valid procedural objections to our reconsideration of the issue now, and, given our recent decision in Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U. S. 304 (2002), we certainly should do so.
In Atkins, we held that the Constitution prohibits the application of the death penalty to mentally retarded persons. The reasons supporting that holding, with one exception, apply with equal or greater force to the execution of juvenile offenders. The exception — the number of States expressly forbidding the execution of juvenile offenders (28) is slightly fewer than the number forbidding the execution of the mentally retarded (30) — does not justify disparate treatment of the two classes. Indeed, the fact that
Rather than repeating the reasoning in our opinion in Atkins, I think it appropriate to quote the following comments from Justice Brennan’s dissenting opinion in Stanford v. Kentucky, 492 U. S., at 394-396, which I joined in 1989:
“Proportionality analysis requires that we compare ‘the gravity of the offense,’ understood to include not only the injury caused, but also the defendant’s culpability, with ‘the harshness of the penalty.’ Solem [v. Helm, 463 U. S. 277, 292 (1983)]. In my view, juveniles so generally lack the degree of responsibility for their crimes that is a predicate for the constitutional imposition of the death penalty that the Eighth Amendment forbids that they receive that punishment.
“Legislative determinations distinguishing juveniles from adults abound. These age-based classifications reveal much about how our society regards juveniles as a class, and about societal beliefs regarding adolescent levels of responsibility. See Thompson [v. Oklahoma, 487 U. S. 815, 823-825 (1988) (plurality opinion)].
“The participation of juveniles in a substantial number of activities open to adults is either barred completely or significantly restricted by legislation. All States but two have a uniform age of majority, and have set that age at 18 or above. ... No State has lowered its voting age below 18. . . . Nor does any State permit a person under 18 to serve on a jury. . . . Only four States ever permit persons below 18 to marry without parental consent.... Thirty-seven States have specific enactments requiring that a patient have attained 18 before she may validly consent to medical treatment. . . . Thirty-four States require parental consent before a person*970 below 18 may drive a motor car. . . . Legislation in 42 States prohibits those under 18 from purchasing pornographic materials. . . . Where gambling is legal, adolescents under 18 are generally not permitted to participate in it, in some or all of its forms. ... In these and a host of other ways, minors are treated differently from adults in our laws, which reflects the simple truth derived from communal experience that juveniles as a class have not the level of maturation and responsibility that we presume in adults and consider desirable for full participation in the rights and duties of modern life.
“ ‘The reasons why juveniles are not trusted with the privileges and responsibilities of an adult also explain why their irresponsible conduct is not as morally reprehensible as that of an adult.’ Thompson, supra, at 835 (plurality opinion). Adolescents ‘are more vulnerable, more impulsive, and less self-disciplined than adults,’ and are without the same ‘capacity to control their conduct and to think in long-range terms.’ Twentieth Century Fund Task Force on Sentencing Policy Toward Young Offenders, Confronting Youth Crime 7 (1978) (hereafter Task Force). They are particularly impressionable and subject to peer pressure, see Eddings v. Oklahoma, 455 U. S. 104, 115 (1982), and prone to ‘experiment, risk-taking and bravado,’ Task Force 3. They lack ‘experience, perspective, and judgment.’ Bellotti v. Baird, 443 U. S. 622, 635 (1979). See generally Thompson, supra, at 835-836, n. 43; Brief for American Society for Adolescent Psychiatry et al. as Amici Curiae (reviewing scientific evidence). Moreover, the very paternalism that our society shows toward youths and the dependency it forces upon them mean that society bears a responsibility for the actions of juveniles that it does not for the actions of adults who are at least theoretically free to make their own choices: ‘youth crime ... is not exclusively the offender’s fault; offenses by the young represent a failure of family, school, and the social system, which share responsibility for the development of America’s youth.’ Task Force 7.
“To be sure, the development of cognitive and reasoning abilities and of empathy, the acquisition of experience upon which these abilities operate and upon which the capacity to make sound value judgments depends, and in general the process of maturation into a self-directed individual fully re*971 sponsible for his or her actions, occur by degrees. See, e. g., G. Manaster, Adolescent Development and the Life Tasks (1977). But the factors discussed above indicate that 18 is the dividing line that society has generally drawn, the point at which it is thought reasonable to assume that persons have an ability to make, and a duty to bear responsibility for their, judgments. Insofar as age 18 is a necessarily arbitrary social choice as a point at which to acknowledge a person’s maturity and responsibility, given the different developmental rates of individuals, it is in fact ‘a conservative estimate of the dividing line between adolescence and adulthood. Many of the psychological and emotional changes that an adolescent experiences in maturing do not actually occur until the early 20s.’ Brief for American Society for Adolescent Psychiatry et al. as Amici Curiae 4 (citing social scientific studies).”
Today, Justice Brennan’s observations are just as forceful and correct as they were in 1989. But even if we were not convinced in 1989, we should be all the more convinced today. Indeed, when determining what legal obligations and responsibilities juveniles will be allowed to take on, the trend tends to require individuals to be older, rather than younger. See, e. g., National Survey of State Laws 418-422, 478-488 (R. Leiter ed., 4th ed. 2003) (reporting that, without exception, all States now require one to be at least 18 in order to marry without parental consent and that all States now require one to be at least 18 to be the age of majority if unmarried). Neuroscientific evidence of the last few years has revealed that adolescent brains are not fully developed, which often leads to erratic behaviors and thought processes in that age group. See Supplemental Brief for Petitioner 8-5. Scientific advances such as the use of functional magnetic resonance imaging — MRI scans — have provided valuable data that serve to make the case even stronger that adolescents “ ‘are more vulnerable, more impulsive, and less self-disciplined than adults.’” Stanford, 492 U. S., at 395.
Moreover, in the last 13 years, a national consensus has developed that juvenile offenders should not be executed. No State has lowered the age of eligibility to either 16 or 17 since our decision in 1989. See V. Streib, The Juvenile Death Penalty Today: Death Sentences and Executions for Juvenile Crimes, January 1, 1973-September 30, 2002, p. 7 (updated Oct. 9, 2002),
All of this leads me to conclude that offenses committed by juveniles under the age of 18 do not merit the death penalty. The practice of executing such offenders is a relic of the past and is inconsistent with evolving standards of decency in a civilized society. We should put an end to this shameful practice.
I would set the application for an original writ for argument and respectfully dissent from the Court’s refusal to do so.
See Ind. Code Ann. §§35-50-2-3, 3(b)(1)(A) (West Supp. 2002); 2002 Ind. Pub. L. 117-2002, § 1.
See Mont. Code Ann. §45-5-102(2) (1997); 1999 Mont. Laws, ch. 523.
See N. Y. Penal Law § 125.27 (West Supp. 2002).
See Kan. Stat. Ann. §21-4622 (1995).
See State v. Furman, 122 Wash. 2d 440, 459, 858 P. 2d 1092, 1103 (1993).
Lead Opinion
Petition for writ of habeas corpus denied.