39 Ala. 254 | Ala. | 1864
Government is ordained of God, and the powers confided to governors are held in trust for the benefit of the governed. This is essentially true of all forms of government. But in this country, the doctrine has been everywhere openly declared, and lies at the foundation of all our institutions. That the ultimate sovereignty resides
The powers confided to government in order to fulfill the general object and intention of providing for the welfare and happiness of the people, and specially enumerated in the constitution of the Confederate States, necessarily vary in their nature and character, according to the subjects to which they relate. Among them, the power of war and peace is, beyond question, that which ranks first in importance. The war-and-peace power, it will be observed by glancing at the constitution, is conferred with great care, and in the most ample manner. It is not contained in any one enumerated power, but forms the subject-matter of six out of the eighteen enumerated powers in terms, and of three of the others by necessary implication. I call it the war-and-peace power, not because there is any power so specially named in the constitution, but because the mode of expression is convenient, and will be understood. This war-and-peace power, conferred on the congress of the Confederate States by .the constitution, with so much care, and in so ample a manner, is the highest and most vital trust confided to that government; because upon its proper exercise the maintenance and protection of every valuable right, whether of individuals, or the body politic, and involving the very existence of both, must, in case of insurrection or foreign invasion, ultimately depend. It is needless to do more than state a proposition which must command the assent of every mind. War is called the ultima ratio, — the last argument — the last reason; because unhappily, in the controversies of nations, when all argument and all reason ends, war begins. The nation which does not mean to submit to the demands of another nation, and has “exhausted the argument,” can do nothing but “ stand by her arms.” With a nation like ourselves, struggling for a national existence with another nation, which affects to treat our struggle as a rebellion, and our people as rebels, the only alternative left is, subjugation or independence.
To fulfill this high trust, we hold it to be the manifest right, and the imperative duty of the government of the Confederate States, to exhaust, if it becomes necessary, the entire military force of the country, in men, money, and every other available material of war ; but especially, to hold under its control, and to employ, aE the mcdes of the country capable of bearing arms, or of performing other military service. Though it may not be necessary to fortify this position by authorities, I prefer to let a few of the eminent men who have written on this subject speak.
Yattel (book 3, ch. 2) says: “Every citizen is bound to serve and defend the State, so far as he is capable. Society cannot otherwise be maintained; and this concurrence for the common defense is one of the principal objects of every political association! Every man capable of carrying arms, should take them up at the first order of him who has -the power of making war. * * * * The public authority raises soldiers, distributes them into different bodies, under the command of generals and other officers, and keeps them on foot as long as it thinks necessary. As every citizen, or subject, is bound to serve the State, the sovereign has a right to enlist’ whom he pleases. No person is naturally exempt from taking up arms in defense of the State, the obligation of every member of society being the same.”
To the same effect is Burlamaqui: “The obligation under which subjects are in this respect, is so vigorous and strong, that, strictly speaking, no man can be exempted from taking up arms when his country calls on him for assistance, and his refusal would be a just reason not to tolerate such a person any longer in society. If, in most governments, there are some subjects exempt from military services, this immunity is not a privilege that belongs to them by right; it is only a toleration that has no force but when there are troops sufficient for the defense of the commonwealth, and the persons to whom it is granted follow some other useful and necessary employment. Excepting this case, in time
And Wheaton: “Of the absolute international rights of States, the most essential ánd important, and that which lies at the foundation of all the rest, is the right of self-preservation. This right necessarily involves all other incidental rights which are essential to give effect to the principal end. Among these is the right of self-defense. This, again, involves the right to require the military service of -all its people ; to levy troops, and maintain a naval force; to build fortifications, and to impose and collect taxes for all these purposes.” — Wheaton’s International Law, 85.
So much for the' right, and now as to the duty: “In the act of association, by virtue, of which a multitude of men form together a state or nation, each individual has entered into engagements with all to promote the general welfare; and all have entered into engagements with each individual to facilitate for him the means of supplying his' necessities, and to promote and defend him. It is manifest that these reciprocal engagements can no otherwise be fulfilled, than by maintaining the political association. The entire nation is, then, obliged to maintain that association; and, as their preservation depends on its continuance, it thence follows, that every nation is obliged to perform the duty of self-preservation.” — "Vattel, book 1, ch. 2, § 16. “The law of God no less enjoins a whole nation to take care of their preservation, than it does private men.” — Burlamaqui, vob 2, p. 157. “It” (the right of self-preservation) “is not only a right with respect to other states, but a duty with respect to its own members, and the most solemn and important which the state owes to them.” — Wheaton’s International Law, book 2, ch. I, § 2.
Mr. Calhoun, following these great authorities, and speaking in special reference to our American governments, uses this emphatic language : “So long as this state of things continues, exigencies will arise, in which the entire poioer and resources of the community will be needed to defend its existence. When this is at stake, every other
When stating thus broadly the general principle, that the state has the right to call into the field ail men capable of bearing arms, we mean it to be understood in reference to that compound system under which we live, and, of course, do not intend to include within the power of the Confederate States those officials of the State governments who may be necessary to the continued existence and'practical operation of those governments.
Having established, upon reason and such eminent authority, that it is both the right and the duty of government, in the execution of its high trust (the war power), to exhaust, if necessary for the public defense, or in other words for self-preservation, “the entire power and resources of the community” (Calhoun), embracing “every citizen or subject capable of carrying arms” (Yattel and Burlama-qui), and from which it is said “none can be lawfully exempt” (Burlamaqui); we approach the question by which the application of the petitioner must be determined, and which may be propounded in this form: Is it within the power of the congress of the Confederate States to grant permanent and irrepealáble exemptions from military service, upon any terms, or any consideration whatsoever ?
It is manifest, upon looking into the question at large, and the nature of government as considered and settled by numerous authorities, that there are certain attributes of sovereignty — certain high functions of government — which the legislature has no right to give or grant away.' They can neither be surrendered nor sold. They cannot be vested in private persons as property, or in the nature of property, by contract or otherwise; but must be kept and held by the legislature, entire and undiminished, for the benefit of the people — the nation — as public functions and attributes of sovereignty. The opinion is held by many of the first legal minds of the country, that the taxing power of government belongs to this class. But, after a protracted struggle between the authorities of the State of Ohio and the judiciary of the United States, over this question, it
Tbe question arose in tbis wise. Tbe legislature of Obio, in 1845, passed a banking law, under wbicb a number of banking corporations were organized, which contained a clause fixing tbe amount of tax tbe banks should pay during tbe continuance of their charters. By a subsequent act, passed in 1851, tbe tax upon tbe banks was increased. Tbe banks denied tbe constitutionabty of tbis latter act, insisting tbat tbe act of 1845 was a contract, and as such was protected from repeal or alteration by tbe 10th section of tbe 1st article of tbe constitution of tbe United States, wbicb forbids tbat any State shall pass laws “impah'ing tbe obligation of contracts.” Tbe discussion of tbis question, wbicb was very animated and protracted, as well as very able and instructive, can be found by consulting tbe following cases: Debott v. Ohio Life Insurance and Trust Co., 1 Ohio St. R. 563; Mechanics’ and Traders’ Br. Bank v. Debott, ib. 591; Knoup v. Pigua Bank, ib. 603 ; Toledo Bank v. Bond, ib. 623. Tbe supreme court of Obio, in these several cases, sometimes varying in tbe form of expression used, decide in general, among other matters not necessary to notice, tbis proposition: Tbat tbe taxing power, wbicb constitutes a branch of tbe legislative power, and wbicb is of vital importance, and essential to tbe existence of government, cannot be surrendered or abandoned, either in whole or in part, by tbe legislature, to promote private and individual interests, so as to limit tbe power and control of future legislation over it; and tbat tbe legislature is incompetent to make any contract or arrangement, whereby tbe legislative power over it can be to any extent surrendered or abridged.
Tbe cases of The Pigua Bank v. Knoup, and The Ohio Life Ins. and Tr. Co. v. Debott, were taken to tbe supreme court of tbe United States. Tbat court, reversing tbe judgment of tbe Obio court, decided — 1st, tbat tbe act of Obio of 1845, chartering tbe banks, in tbe clause fixing tbe tax
As one of the results of the reasoning employed in his opinion, Judge Catron lays down the following: “That according to the constitutions of all the States of this Union, and even of the British parliament, the sovereign political power is not the subject of contract, so as to be vested in an irrepealable charter of incorporation, and taken away from and placed beyond the reach of future legislation; that the taxing power is a political power of the highest class, and each successive legislature, having invested in it, unimpaired, all the political powers previous legislatures had, is authorized to impose taxes on all property in the State that its constitution does not exempt.” Although Judge Campbell does not base his dissent upon the ground that no such contract could be lawfully made by the legislature, but only on the ground that, by a true construction of the act, no contract was in fact made, his reasoning is so apposite to the first ground, that I quote a portion of it: “ The powers of that assembly in general, and that of taxation especially,- are trust powers, held by them as magistrates in deposit, to be returned after a short period to their constituents, without abuse or diminution. The nature of the legislative authority is inconsistent with an inflexible, stationary system of administration. Its officé is one of vigilance over the varying wants and changing elements of the association, to the end of ameliorating its condition. Every general assembly is organized with the charge of the legislative powers of the State; each is
The question afterwards assumed a new form. In 1851, after the institution of the case of Piqua Bank v. Knoup and others, the people of Ohio made a change in their constitution, in. which they incorporated an article declaring, in effect, that the legislature should levy a tax on. the property and effects of all banks and other corporations, which should make the burden of taxation on them pro-portionably equal to that borne by all other property. This was aimed at the provision in these bank charters, which fixed a certain limit to taxation. The case of Dodge v. Woolsey, (18 Howard, 331,) in which the old question was presented under this new aspect, was carried to the supreme court. It was urged, that, as the people of Ohio had changed their constitution, so as to make it the duty of the legislature to make all taxes proportionably equal, and a law had been passed in 1852 raising the tax on the banks in order to carry out this provision, the 10th section of the 1st article of the constitution of the United States, in relation to “ laws impairing the obligation of contracts,” could no longer apply. But the majority of the supreme court adhered to their former decision, and declared that the provisions of the charter granted in 1845 were still in force. Judge Campbell delivered a very able dissenting opinion, in which Judges Catron and Daniel concurred. We give the following extract from his opinion: “ My conclusion is, that the constitution of Ohio, whether it be regarded as the expression of the sovereign will of the people, that the extraordinary fexemption granted to these corporations, by which they contribute unequally to the public support, is contrary to the genius of their institutions; or, whether they are inconsistent with a just apportionment of the public burdens; or whether as a declaration of the exigency of the State requiring an additional contribution from them
I would refer those who desire to pursue the subject of this Ohio controversy, to the opinion of Bartley, C. J., of Ohio, in the case of The Toledo Bank v. Bond, (supra,) in which the decision in the celebrated Dartmouth College case (4 Wheaton, 518) is examined and combated, and the whole subject of legislative contracts made with corporations is discussed with great fullness and ability.
But, many years before the decision of the Ohio cases, this same question in relation to the taxing power arose and was mooted in the State of New Hampshire, in the case of Brewster v. Hough, 10 N. H. 138. In that case, Parker, O. J., holds this language: “ The power of taxation is essentially a power of sovereignty, or eminent domain ; and it may well deserve consideration, whether this power is not inherent in the people under a republican government, and so far inalienable that no legislature can make a contract by which it shall be surrendered, without express authority for that purpose in the constitution, or some other way directly from the people themselves.”
In view of this divided state of legal opinion, I think it may be fairly claimed, that the question, whether the taxing power is not one of those great attributes of sovereignty which cannot be finally surrendered or impaired by an ordinary act of legislation, still remains in duhio, and the contest over it is open to be renewed at any time, by those who hold that it is, without disrespect to the settled decisions of the courts. One observation to be made here is, that if the same question were made under an act of congress in respect to limitations on the taxing power, it is by no means certain that the same court would feel bound to make the same decision as that made in the Ohio cases* In the first place, the constitutional provision in respect to “laws impairing the obligation of contracts,” is in terms limited to the “ States,” and does not include the United States. In the second place, the war power being surrendered by the States, and confided ip. the United States, by
But, whatever may be the law in regard to legislative limitations on the taxing power, there are unquestionably certain high attributes of sovereignty, which do not allow of any such limitations. Among these may be mentioned the right of eminent domain. And what is the right of eminent domain? It is thus described by Yattel (book 7, ch. 20): “ The right which belongs to the society, or to the sovereign, of disposing in case of necessity, and for the public safety, of all the wealth contained in the State, is called the eminent domain.” Under the provisions of the constitution of the Confederate States, one limitation, and one only, is placed on this right; and that is the provision which declares, that “ private property shall not be taken for public use, without just compensation. ” — Art. 1, sec. 7, § 13. With this limitation, there is nothing which bears the nature of property, whether real or personal, corporeal or incorporeal, which may not be taken and used Under it, for the public good in peace, or the public defense in war. The books are full of cases involving the question of its nature and extent; and the current of decision is uniform and unbroken, that no limitation can be placed upon it by any power or right, private or public, but that Which has been named. It cannot be surrendered by legislative grant, or contracted away for a consideration, under legislative contracts. One legislature cannot vest in its grantees or beneficiaries land, or goods, or corporate franchises, no matter what may be their nature or kind, so securely that a succeeding legislature cannot take and appropriate them afterwards for the public use, if necessity requires, upon making compensation; and of the existence of such necessity, each succeeding legislature must be the judge.
The doctrine of eminent domain was largely discussed in the case of the West River Bridge v. Dix et al., (6 Howard, 507,) which case went to the full extent of deciding, that not only the land and other material property of an incorporation might be taken, but their franchise also. It
These principles have been settled in a great number of cases; and it is believed that no respectable authority can be found which conflicts with them. — See the following cases: Charles River Bridge v. Warren Bridge, 11 Peters, 546; Beckman v. S. & S. Railroad, 3 Paige, 45 ; Rogers v. Bradshaw, 20 Johns. 742; Boston Water P. Co. v. Worcester R. R., 23 Pick. 360; Tuckahoe Canal case, 11 Leigh, 75; Crosby v. Hanover, 36 N. H. 404; 7 N. H. 35 ; 10 N. H. 138; 7 Foster, (N. H.) 183; Dyer v. Tuskaloosa Bridge Co., 2 Porter, 297; Young v. McKenzie, 3 Kelly, (Geo.) 31; 2 Gray, (Mass.) 2; 14 Illinois R. 314; 31 Penn. R. 37; 1 Sneed. (Tenn.) 176.
A question here presents itself, the answer to which must determine this controversy. Do not all states possess a sovereign attribute, by which they have the right to command and control the personal services of their citizens, for the public defense, in case of war or insurrection, which is not distinguishable in principle from the right of eminent domain over property ? That they have the right, and that it is their duty, if the public safety requires, to call into the field their entire male .population — “all men” — “every man” —“eA^ery resident citizen or subject” — the authorities we have already quoted conclusively prove. Wheaton says, the state “has the right to require military service of all its people-” Yattel, that “every man capable of bearing arms should take them up at the first order of him who has the power of making war,” and that “no person is naturally exempted from taking up arms in defense of the state;” Burlamaqui, that “ no man can be exempted from taking up arms, when his country calls on him for assistance;” Calhoun, that “exigencies will arise, in Avhich the entire power and resources of the community will be needed to defend its existence. When this is at stake, every other consideration must yield to it. Self-preservation is the supreme law, as well with communities as individuals.” The reason for giving to the right this broad and sweeping extent, is pithily stated by Mr. Monroe, as quoted in Jeffers v. Fair (32 Geo. R.) : “The
When we come to consider the nature of the trust confided to government in the due exercise of this great power, it must be confessed that this is .of higher importance than that over property, because the latter relates mainly to the proper administration of affairs and the well-being of the state in time of peace, and the former to the very existence and preservation of the state when threatened with war and subjugation; and if it be incompatible with the nature of the one, as has been conclusively shown, to suffer any positive diminution or limitation, even under the influence of the most solemn legislative contracts, the same principle must hold good, with even greater reason, in case of the other. If it has been wisely determined, that one legislature has not, and can not have, the power to bind succeeding legislatures, by contract or otherwise, so as to exempt absolutely any property, real or personal, from the right of eminent domain; what reason can there be, on principle, in holding that one legislature shall have the power to bind its successors, by irrepealable exemptions, from exercising that more vital and essential sovereign attribute, the right to call into the field every citizen of the state, should the public safety require it? Does a man cease to be a citizen, because the law, for reasons of public policy, gives him for the time an exemption from military service? Until he ceases to be a citizen, with the rights and the duties which
Precedents and decisions on this subject are not common, for the question has never been brought to a decision in England, so far as we can find, and in this country very rarely until lately. Although the principles which govern the case, as we have shown, are old, and long established, there seem to have been few occasions on which it was necessary to give, them application. This may have arisen from the fact, that it has been rarely found necessary to revoke exemptions alleged to be founded on contract; or from the fact that, in view of those fundamental principles which govern the relation of citizen and state, few have thought it necessary to contest the sovereign attribute in subordination to which all exemptions are, and must ever remain, revocable.
“The only quéstion, therefore, is, whether the legislature had power, under these circumstances, to revoke the exemption formerly enjoyed by Bird, and to require him to do duty among the conditional exempts. We are not prepared to say that one set of legislators can control their successors to this extent, in a case of such vital importance to the commonwealth. There may, undoubtedly, be cases in which it might be deemed a breach of the public faith to revoke such exemptions; and it is not to be supposed that the legislature would do it, in any case, without very powerful motives. But we are not authorized to weigh those motives, or to suffer them to have any influence on our decision, when the law is clearly and unequivocally expressed. We cannot, in this case, allow the exemption claimed by the respondent, without deciding that the legislature cannot, under any circumstances, require the services of an individual who has once been exempted. We must say, that an able-bodied citizen, whose services in the militia have been dispensed with, or commuted, in time of peace and tranquillity, can never afterwards be compelled to lend his
This case, and the grounds taken in the opinion of the court, I hold to be a good authority to show that all exemptions from service are revocable. By the same rule, and the same reasoning, the legislature could revoke the exemptions even of those who had performed service under the law of 1810, for the full term of five years; and yet that would as clearly be an exemption under a legislative contract, as in a case of substitution.
Military exemptions commonly are not, and rightfully and lawfully cannot be, granted as a boon or privilege. They proceed on the ground of public policy, and are intended to subserve the public interests.. All men cannot go to the field, even those who are able-bodied. The country, in war, as well as in peace, indispensably requires that a large number of such men should remain at home, to govern the state, and keep in active operation agriculture and the mechanic arts, and the interests of education and religion, as subsidiary to the great work of defending the public liberties. Such exemptions, as they ought never to be granted except on grounds of public policy, so ought never to be revoked except upon, the like ground of public policy. More grace and favor in granting, or mere caprice and oppression in revoking, are unworthy motives not to be imputed to the legislature. It is their duty (and to this, and this only, are they bound), to deal with the whole question in good faith, as the representatives of the people, holding in their hands the high and solemn trust of defending to the best of their abilities the liberties of the country. And if they but observe good faith, there can be no exempt tion granted, but what may be revoked by the same or a subsequent legislature.
We have not deemed it necessary to discuss the question, whether or not, under a proper construction of the act of congress which grants exemption to those who furnish substitutes, the power is left in congress to revoke at pleasure such exemptions by virtue of the act itself. Differences of opinion on this question, it is manifest,' prevail in the country; and as there were, in our judgment, higher and firmer
I sum up the views we hold on the questions involved in this inquiry, in the following propositions:
1. That the war-and-peace power, conferred on the congress of the Confederate States by the constitution, is the highest and most vital trust confided to that government; because upon its proper exercise the maintenance and protection of every valuable right, whether of individuals or the body politic, and involving the very existence of both, must, in case of insurrection or foreign invasion, ultimately depend.
2. That, to execute this high trust, it is the imperative duty, as it is the manifest right of that government, to exhaust, if it becomes necessary, the entire military force of the country, in men, money, and every other available material of war; but especially to hold under its control and to employ all the males of the country capable of bearing arms, or of performing other military service.
3. That, in view of thi3 high trust and this great correlative duty, conferred and imposed upon that government for the public defense and the preservation of life, liberty and property, it is not in the power of any congress to grant permanent and irrepealafile exemptions from military service, upon any terms, or any consideration whatever; but that all exemptions granted by congress, must be taken under the implied condition that, if the exigencies of the country require, they may be revoked and set aside; and that each successive congress must be the judge of what the public defense and the necessities of the country from time to time require.
4. Proceeding upon these principles, we decide, that the act of congress of January 5th, 1864, which declares, “-that no person shall be exempted from military service by reason of his having furnished a substitute,” and the act of February 17th, 1864, which repeals all previous exemptions, both have the effect of repealing so much of the act of April 16th, 1862, as allows an exemption to any one fur
The decree of the chancellor, refusing to discharge the petitioner, is affirmed.
While it is not my intention to write a dissenting opinion in this case, I wish it understood that I do not commit myself to the opinion or arguments of my brothers. I wish this published with the opinion of the court, if I do not file a more extended opinion.