56 Miss. 269 | Miss. | 1879
delivered the opinion of the court.
Adeline Cunningham was convicted, in the Circuit Court of Clay County, of the murder of her husband, and sentenced to be hung.
That she committed the deed, and that it was one of peculiar atrocity, is not denied nor gainsaid.
In the dead hour of night, while the husband lay sleeping on the common bed, she split open his head with a hatchet, without provocation or motive, so far as can be ascertained. She waited quietly till morning came, and then freely and voluntarily avowed the act to all inquirers, offering no excuse,, save that to one person she stated that her husband was attempting to take her life with a knife, which, she said, would be found in the bed, but which could nowhere be discovered.
The defence set up for her is temporary or periodic insanity, produced by derangement in her monthly menstruations, and which it is said was liable to attack her at each recurring monthly period.
Without desiring to express any opinion on the facts, it is proper to say that there was sufficient evidence to suggest at
.They were not so left. By the first instruction given forl^ the State, they were informed that “ the legal presumption of sanity is not overcome by the mere probability that the party was insane, but will stand until overthrown by evidence. Mere probability of insanity cannot prevail over the presumption of sanity, so as to work the acquittal of the party on the ground of insanity. For a defence resting on the ground of insanity, the insanity must be clearly proved.”
In other words, the jury were told that though they believed the defendant probably insane, she must be convicted on some presumption of law which overthrew all probabilities of fact.
Is this a sound principle of law? Undoubtedly there are numerous authorities which so declare, as there are many also going far beyond this, and holding that the defence of insanity can never avail unless its existence is established to the exclusion of every reasonable doubt. There is perhaps no subject connected with criminal law upon which the authorities are more hopelessly in conflict than the one here presented?-
Three distinct theories are held by courts and text-writers of the highest character, and each may be supported by a long array of respectable authorities, viz. : 1. The prisoner must prove his insanity beyond a reasonable doubt, 2. He must establish it by a preponderance of evidence, 3. He must raise a reasonable doubt as to his sanity,
The first of these views receives most countenance from English adjudications and text-books ; the second is supported by a majority of the American courts ; while the third, though held as yet perhaps by a minority of the adjudged cases, is gaining in favor, is the well-settled law in many of the States^ and is supported by a power of reasoning which we deem convincing.
Every indictment charges the commission of a criminal act by a responsible being, and no conviction can occur until the
Hence, in the absence of evidence to suggest the contrary, the jury acts on this presumption, and, the deed being proven, the conviction follows. But if. in proving the deed, evidence is offered which suggests a doubt of the party’s sanity, the State must promptly meet it, and this without regard to the side from which the proof suggesting the doubt comes_._v TEe law clothes the accused wltFa presumption of innocence which he never loses until a verdict of conviction has been pronounced. He pleads nothing affirmatively, save in rare and exceptional instances, but by his plea of not guilty he puts upon the State the burden of establishing every fact necessary to constitute guilt. The changing phases of the evidence may make his case at various stages wear various aspects. At one moment it may seem that his guilt has been conclusively shown, and at the next it may appear to have been as conclusively negatived ; but his own attitude never changes. To every fresh development and every new circumstance he repeats his plea of not guilty, and in every new complication he rests upon his legal presumption of innocence. The testimony offered against him may, indeed, necessitate the production of something on his part to meet the case as made out; but it can never do this until, uncontradicted and unexplained, it has demonstrated his guilt beyond a reasonable doubt. Shall it be said that, because this has been accomplished at some particular stage of the testimony, the burden of proof has shifted, ¿and thenceforward the duty is imposed upon him of reestablishing his innocence beyond all reasonable doubt? Nobody would venture so to assert, if the demonstration of guilt so made out was in regard to the commission of the act? Why should the rule be different in reference to the mental account
The presumptions or implications which, in criminal cases, the law deduces from the establishment of particular facts, have no other force than to dispense with further proof of the thing presumed, unless something in the testimony, either theretofore or thereafter offered, suggests a doubt of the existence of the presumed fact. But the moment that doubt is engendered in reference to it, if it be as to a fact necessary to conviction, the State must establish the fact independently of the presumption ; and the obligation to do this rests continuously upon her. The accused need do nothing save repose upon the presumption of innocence with which the law has clothed him, and claim the benefit of all the doubts which the testimony has evolved.
Apply these principles to the question of sanity. Because^ he is a human being, the accused is presumed to be sane. He must be sane in order to be guilty. The trial commences with • the presumption that he is so. If nothing in the testimony suggests otherwise, there is no obligation to establish it; but the moment the proof warrants a reasonable doubt of it, np matter from which side it comes, that doubt must be remoyed. Which side must remove it? Manifestly that side which set out to show guilt, because there can be no guilt without sanity.^, That condition of sanity which is ordinarily the attribute of all men has been rendered doubtful as to this particular man, and, as his guilt depends upon his sanity, its existence must be shown in the same manner, and to the same extent, as any of the other elements which go to make up the crime. What logic or con
We think the true rule is this : Every man is presumed to be sane, and, in the absence of testimony engendering a reasonable doubt of sanity, no evidence on the subject need be offered; but whenever the question of sanity is raised and put in issue by such facts, proven on either side, as engender such doubt, it devolves upon the State to remove it, and to establish the sanity of the prisoner to the satisfaction of the jury, beyond all reasonable doubt arising out of all the evidence in the case. Pollard v. The State, 53 Miss. 410; The People v. McCann, 16 N. Y. 58; The State v. Bartlett, 43 N. H. 224; The State v. Crawford, 11 Kan. 32; Polk v. The State, 19 Ind. 170; Hopps v. The State, 31 Ill. 385; Ogletree v. The State, 28 Ala. (n. s.) 701.
When we speak of insanity as an excuse for crime, we refer, of course, to such degree of insanity as disqualifies from a proper perception of the difference between right and wrong, and thereby shields its victim from legal accountability for his acts. Bovard’s Gase, 30 Miss. 600.
We find in the record, among the instructions asked by the defendant, one numbered twelve, in which the rule here laid down is announced, to wit, that the jury must acquit if they
The ninth instraction asked by the defendant, and refused by the court, was in these words : “ Where the delusion of a party is such that he has a real and firm belief of the existence of a fact which is wholly imaginary, and under that insane belief he has done an act which would be justifiable if such fact existed, he is not responsible for such act. Nor is a pai'ty responsible for an act done under an uncontrollable impulse which is the result of mental disease.”
The doctrine announced in the first clause of this instruction first found distinct utterance in the celebrated prosecution of Hadfield for the attempted assassination of King George III. (20 How. St. Tr. 1281), and owes its birth and adoption into the English law to the genius and eloquence of Erskine. It has been repeatedly since recognized, both in England and America, notably in this country in The Commonwealth v. Rogers, 7 Metc. 500, and in Roberts v. The State, 3 Ga. 310. Of its correctness there can, we think, be no doubt. Indeed, though it has by some courts been denied recognition, it seems to us only another method of stating that there can be no crime where there is a mental incapacity to distinguish between right and wrong; for, though delusions as to particular matters frequently exist in minds which are perfectly rational upon all other subjects, yet, if the delusion be, so fixed and vivid as to make the imaginary seem the real, there must' be upon that subject, a total incapacity to distinguish between right and wrong, since, the entire relation between the victim of the delusion and its unconscious subject being mentally perverted, there can be no proper standard of right and wrong in the
If a crazed enthusiast violates the law, impelled by a madness which makes him deem it the inspired act of God, he has only done that which his diseased and deluded imagination taught him was right; and if the act would be proper in one so divinely inspired, and was the direct and necessary consequence of the delusion, there can be no punishment, because, however rational on other subjects, he was on that subject incapable of having a criminal intent.
The juries must, under the instructing guidance of the courts, be the judges of the sincerity and firmness of the belief, and of whether the act was in truth the direct and necessary result of the insane delusion. There is but little danger that the sober common sense of mankind will be deceived by a feigned madness, or will fail to detect the craftiest impostor who, under the guise of insanity, violates the criminal law. The danger rather is, that indignation at the crime, and incapacity to appreciate the delusion, will make them incredulous of its existence.
We think that the first clause of the instruction, which is taken substantially from the opinion of Chief Justice Shaw in The Commonwealth v. Rogers, supra, announces a correct principle of law.
The second clause declares that there is no responsibility for “ an • act committed under the uncontrollable impulse resulting from mental disease.” If the impulse meant is the direct result of such mental disease as destroys the perception of right and wrong, this is only a reaffirmation of the
This character of insanity is variously styled moral, or emotional, or impulsive, or paroxysmal insanity. It is known among medical writers as lesion of the will. Its peculiarity is said to be that, while the mental perception is unimpaired, the mind is powerless to control the will; that while its unhappy subject knows the right, and desires to pursue it, some mysterious and uncontrollable impulse compels him to commit the wrong. This kind of insanity, if insanity it can be called, though sometimes recognized by respectable courts, and still oftener, perhaps, by juries seeking an excuse to evade the stern dictates of the law, is properly rejected by the authorities generally. The possibility of the existence of such a mental condition is too doubtful, the theory is too problematical, and too incapable of a practical solution, to afford a safe basis of legal adjudication. It may serve as a metaphysical or psychological problem, to interest and amuse the speculative philosopher, but it must be discarded by the jurist and the law-giver in the practical affairs of life. To it may well be applied the language of Judge Curtis, who, in speaking of this and similar questions, says: “ They are an important, as well as a deeply interesting, study, and they find their place in that science which ministers to diseases pf the mind. * * * But the law is not a medical nor a metaphysical science. Its search is after those practical rules which may be administered without inhumanity, for the security of civil society by protecting it from crime. And therefore it inquires, not injo the peculiar constitution of mind of the accused, or what weakness, or even disorders, he was afflicted with, but solely whether he was
The latter clause of the instruction in question is copied — as, indeed, the whole instruction is — from the syllabus, or head-notes, of The Commonwealth v. Rogers, 7 Metc. 500, but it fails to embody the qualification and restriction thrown around the doctrine in the opinion itself.
The uncontrollable impulse which the learned chief justice declares will excuse the act is said to be that “ which overwhelms reason, conscience, and judgment.” “ If so,” says he, “ then the act was not the act of a voluntary agent, but the involuntary act of the body, without the concurrence of the mind directing it.” In other words, it is the uncontrollable act of a mind destitute of reason, conscience, or judgment as to the particular object, however sane as to other matters. The latter clause of the instruction, therefore, should have been restricted by words conveying the idea that the act was the direct result of an uncontrollable impulse, springing from mental disease, existing to so high a degree that for the time it overwhelmed the reason, judgment, and conscience.
The exceptions taken to the action of the court in its rulings on the evidence are without merit.
For the errors indicated in the instructions, the judgment is reversed and a new trial awarded;