64 Mass. 397 | Mass. | 1852
The single question presented by the record here, is, whether an indictment can be sustained for the larcenious taking of money, which the party, from whom it is
It has been very ingeniously argued by the defendant’s counsel, that money, so obtained, is destitute of the rights of property, and being thus in a manner outlawed, is not entitled to legal protection, and is incapable of being the subject-matter of larceny; in a word, that it may be stolen with absolute impunity.
We might have supposed the question to be precluded by the provision of the statute, which enacts, that, in the prosecution of any offence committed in stealing, embezzling, destroying, inj uring, or fraudulently receiving or concealing any money or other chattels, it shall be sufficient, and shall not be deemed a variance, if it be proved on the trial, that at the time when the offence was committed, either the actual or constructive possession, or the general or special property, in the whole or in any part of the money or chattels, was in the person alleged in the indictment to be the owner thereof. Rev. Sts. c. 133, § 11. By force of this statute, certainly, whatever might be the rule at common law, the question of variance no longer depends exclusively on the proof of property, either general or special, of the thing stolen; for that is but one of the alternative conditions of the statute; the other being possession merely. It is admitted in reply, that possession is primá facie evidence of property; and then it is argued that, as evidence, this may be rebutted by proof of the actual fact, to wit, of property in some person other than the one named in the indictment; and the case is put of possession by the servant, and proof of property in the master. But these are questions technical merely, of pleading or variance, not of principle.
We apprehend it would be no answer to an indictment for larceny properly drawn, to say that the object larceniously taken, belonged to nobody, provided the thing were in its nature property; 2 East, P. C. 606; 2 Russ. on Crimes, (6th Am. ed.) 96; or that it belonged to some unknown owner; for then, by force of the statute, and by common law too, it would be protected in the hands of the possessor. But
We fully recognize the soundness of this doctrine, supported as it is by obvious considerations of public policy and justice. But the inference, deduced therefrom in argument, by no means follows. That same common law, which, in its integrity and wisdom, refuses to lend itself to be the instrument, even indirectly, for the execution of a criminal contract, will as little condescend to throw its mantle over crime itself. The law punishes larceny, because it is larceny; and, therefore, one may be convicted of theft, though he do but steal his own property, from himself or his bailee. 7 H. VI. 43 a; 3 Co. Inst. 110. And the law punishes the larceny of property, not solely because of any rights of the proprietor, but also because of its own inherent legal rights as property; and, therefore, even he, who larceniously takes the stolen object from a thief whose hands have but just closed upon it, may himself be convicted therefor, in spite of the criminality of the possession of his immediate predecessor in crime. This principle is coeval with the common law itself as a collection of received opinions and rules, for we have to go back to the Year-Books to find its first judicial announcement. The leading decision is the case of a so-called John at Stile, in 13 Edw. IV. 3 b., where it was held by the judges that if A. steal the goods of B., and afterwards C. steal the same goods from A., in such case C. is indictable both as to A. and as to B. This decision was afterwards affirmed arguendo in 4 Hen. VII. 5 b. The argument in the Year-Books, it is true, turns on the point of the property not being changed by the two successive
In a later case at the Old Bailey, there is a ruling supposed, by some, to be in conflict with the preceding; but not so in fact, for several reasons; more especially in that the latter case is one of embezzlement, not of larceny. Regina v. Hunt, 8 Car. & P. 642.
We do not say our doctrine is good law, merely because it was in principle so adjudged in the time of the Plantagenets and the Tudors; but we say it is good law, also, because it is reasonable and just; because every subsequent authority in England, such as Hale, 1 Hale, P. C. (Am. ed.) 507; East, 2 East, P. C. 654; Russell, 2 Russ. on Crim. (6th Am. ed.) 89, has adopted and approved it; because it has-been affirmed by modern judicial opinion in England ; Wilkins’s case, 2 Leach, 586; because it has already been recognized in the United States; Ward v. The People, 3 Hill, 396; and because it thus bears that genuine stamp of venerable time, which consists, not in the antiquity of date—for there may be old errors as well as new ones—but in having stood the test of the scrutiny of many successive ages. We think it is well established at common law, therefore, that property, though unlawfully acquired, may nevertheless be the subject-matter of larceny; and we think the cases decided are broad enough to cover the present or any similar form of unlawful acquisition. So well persuaded
1. It is fundamental, in our own and in all other laws of property, that the possession of one is good against all others, who cannot show a better right of possession. It is the rule of strictly technical law, not less than of general theory. Thus, it has been expressly decided by this court, in a plea of land, that, as between two persons, each of whom entered without right, the older trespasser can maintain his possession by law as against the younger one, although he himself be subject to be ousted at will by the true tenant in fee. Hubbard v. Little, 9 Cush. 475. This illustration of the legal effect of actual possession of land is directly applicable to the present point, with the qualification only, that possession of chattels, particularly money, would have still stronger arguments of legal convenience in its favor.
2. If, looking beyond the mere question of property, we pass to considerations of public policy, this may be regarded in two points of view, one, of convenience in the administration of justice, the other, of higher ethical relation. As to the former point, it is not easy to conceive any thing, which would more seriously embarrass the public ministers of justice, and obstruct its administration, than if it were held that any element of illegality in the acquisition of property rendered it incapable of being the subject of larceny, and if, as a consequence, the necessity followed, in every case, to go into the inquiry how the party complaining acquired the property.
As to the latter point, if the question be put in the form most favorable to the argument for the defendant here, it stands thus : Of the alternative moral and social evils, which is the greater,—to deprive property unlawfully acquired of all protection as such, and thus to discourage unlawful acquisition but encourage larceny; or to punish, and so discourage
Exceptions overruled.